Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 174, Issue 6, pp 1605–1616 | Cite as

Prospective interpretation

  • Zoltán Gendler SzabóEmail author
Article

Abstract

Semantic and pragmatic theories tend to deal with context-change in two radically opposing ways. Some view it as theoretically irrelevant, interpreting each sentence relative to the context as it happens to be at the moment of its utterance. Others view it as theoretically fundamental, proposing to view context-change as the very subject-matter of the theory of interpretation. Robert Stalnaker’s book Context steers a middle course between the extremes–to keep the semantics mostly static while letting the pragmatics go mostly dynamic. Within his framework, context-change matters because interpretation is sometimes prospective, relying not on the context as it is at the time of utterance but on the context as it is anticipated to be somewhat later. This paper critically examines how Stalnaker makes use of prospective interpretation in accounting for accommodation and in capturing the insights of expressivism.

Keywords

Accommodation Context Expressivism Presupposition Speech acts 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Mike Deigan, Tamar Szabó Gendler, Kate Stanton, and Jason Stanley for their comments. Special thanks to the participants of the UConn workshop on Context for discussion. Extra special thanks to Bob Stalnaker for his response to an earlier draft at the same workshop.

References

  1. Abbott, B. (2008). Presuppositions and common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 523–538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Gauker, C. (1998). What is a context of utterance? Philosophical Studies, 91, 149–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition, and logical form. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  4. Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), The logic of grammar (pp. 64–75). Encino, CA: Dickenson. (Reprinted in Grice 1989, pp. 22–41. Page references to the reprinted version).Google Scholar
  5. Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Heim, I. (1991). Artikel und Definitheit. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantik: Ein Internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung (pp. 487–535). Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  7. Horn, L. (2007). Toward a fregean pragmatics: Voraussetzung, nebengedanke, andeutung. In I. Kecskés & L. Horn (Eds.), Explorations in pragmatics: Linguistic, cognitive, and intercultural aspects (pp. 39–69). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  8. Horn, L., & Abbott, B. (2012). <the, a>: (In)definiteness and implicature. In J. Campbell et al. (Eds.), Reference and referring: Topics in contemporary philosophy (Vol. 10, pp. 325–357). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Langendoen, D. T., & Savin, H. B. (1971). The projection problem for presuppositions. In C. Fillmore & D. T. Langendoen (Eds.), Studies in linguistic semantics (pp. 54–60). New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.Google Scholar
  10. Lewis, D. (1975). A problem about permission. In E. Saarinen et al. (Eds.), Essays in honor of Jaako Hintikka (pp. 163–75). Dordrecht: Reidel. (Reprinted in Lewis 2000, pp. 20–33. Page references to the reprinted version).Google Scholar
  11. Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 339–359. (Reprinted in Lewis 1983, pp. 233–49. Page references to the reprinted version).Google Scholar
  12. Lewis, D. (1983). Philosophical papers I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Lewis, D. (2000). Papers in ethics and social philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Soames, S. (1982). How presuppositions are inherited: A solution to the projection problem. Linguistic Inquiry, 13, 483–545.Google Scholar
  15. Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Stalnaker, R. (1974) Pragmatic presupposition. In M. Munitz & P. Unger (Eds.), Semantics and philosophy (pp. 197–213). New York: New York University Press. (Reprinted in Stalnaker 1999, pp. 47–62).Google Scholar
  17. Stalnaker, R. (1975). A theory of conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269–286. (Reprinted in Stalnaker 1999, pp. 63–77).Google Scholar
  18. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, (Vol. 9, pp. 315–332). (Reprinted in Stalnaker 1999, pp. 78–95).Google Scholar
  19. Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Stalnaker, R. (2008). A response to Abbott on presupposition and common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 539–544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Stalnaker, R. (2011). Conditional propositions and conditional assertions. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 227–248). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Stalnaker, R. (2014). Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Szabó, Z. G. (2006) Comments on Kai von Fintel’s paper ‘What is presupposition accommodation, again?’. Available at http://pragmatics.osu.edu/.
  24. von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The king of France is back! Presuppositions and truth-value intuitions. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 315–341). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. von Fintel, K. (2008). What is presupposition accommodation again? Philosophical Perspectives: Philosophy of Language, 22, 137–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Yale UniversityNew HavenUSA

Personalised recommendations