Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 173, Issue 11, pp 3037–3060 | Cite as

“Actual” does not imply “feasible”

  • Nicholas Southwood
  • David Wiens
Article

Abstract

The familiar complaint that some ambitious proposal is infeasible naturally invites the following response: Once upon a time, the abolition of slavery and the enfranchisement of women seemed infeasible, yet these things were actually achieved. Presumably, then, many of those things that seem infeasible in our own time may well be achieved too and, thus, turn out to have been perfectly feasible after all. The Appeal to History, as we call it, is a bad argument. It is not true that if some desirable state of affairs was actually achieved, then it was feasible that it was achieved. “Actual” does not imply “feasible,” as we put it. Here is our objection. “Feasible” implies “not counterfactually fluky.” But “actual” does not imply “not counterfactually fluky.” So, “actual” does not imply “feasible.” While something like the Flukiness Objection is sometimes hinted at in the context of the related literature on abilities, it has not been developed in any detail, and both premises are inadequately motivated. We offer a novel articulation of the Flukiness Objection that is both more precise and better motivated. Our conclusions have important implications, not only for the admissible use of history in normative argument, but also by potentially circumscribing the normative claims that are applicable to us.

Keyword

Feasibility Appeal to History Flukiness Objection 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Previous versions of this paper were presented at the Australian National University, the University of California San Diego, the Association for Political Theory annual conference and the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference. We are very grateful to many friends and colleagues for their valuable feedback. We would particularly like to thank Christian Barry, Jesse Driscoll, Pablo Gilabert, Bob Goodin, Benjamin Kiesewetter, Colleen Murphy, Seth Lazar and an anonymous referee for this journal for detailed written comments. Research for the paper was supported by DP120101507 and DP140102468.

References

  1. Austin, J. L. (1956). Ifs and cans. Proceedings of the British Academy, 42, 107–132.Google Scholar
  2. Barry, C., & Southwood, N. (2011). What is special about human rights? Ethics and International Affairs, 25, 369–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Beitz, C. (2009). The idea of human rights. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bratman, M. (2009). Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In J. Timmerman, J. Skorupski, & S. Robertson (Eds.), Spheres of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Brennan, G. (2013). Feasibility in optimizing ethics. Social Philosophy and Policy, 30, 314–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brennan, G., & Nicholas S. (2007). Feasibility in action and attitude. In: T. Rønnow-Rasmussen, B. Petersson, J. Jonefsson, & D. Egonsson (Eds.) Hommage à Wlodek: Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz, pp 1–25.Google Scholar
  7. Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Estlund, D. (2011). Human nature and the limits (If Any) of political philosophy. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39, 207–237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Estlund, D. (2014). Utopophobia. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 42, 113–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gheaus, A. (2013). The feasibility constraint on the concept of justice. The Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 445–464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gilabert, P. (2011). Feasibility and socialism. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 19, 52–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Gilabert, P. (2012). From global poverty to global equality: A philosophical exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gilabert, P., & Lawford-Smith, H. (2012). Political feasibility: A conceptual exploration. Political Studies, 60, 809–825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Goodin, R. (1982). Political theory and public policy. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  16. Goodin, R., & Pettit, P. (1995). “Introduction” A companion to contemporary political philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1992). In defense of explanatory ecumenism. Economics and Philosophy, 8, 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Maier, J. (2014). Abilities. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/abilities/.
  19. Kolodny, N. (2005). Why be rational? Mind, 114, 509–563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Lawford-Smith, H. (2012). The feasibility of collectives’ action. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 453–467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Lawford-Smith, H. (2013). Understanding political feasibility. Journal of Political Philosophy, 21, 243–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Lyon, A. (2011). Deterministic probability: Neither chance nor credence. Synthese, 182, 413–432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. McCann, H. (1991). Settled objectives and rational constraints. American Philosophical Quarterly, 28, 25–36.Google Scholar
  24. Miller, D. (2013). Justice for earthlings: Essays in political philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Nolan, S. (2013). Angelina Jolie and William Hague Team Up: Britain’s £10million bid to fight sex attacks in war zones. Daily Mail, 11 April 2013.Google Scholar
  26. Pogge, T. (2005). Severe poverty as a violation of negative duties. Etics and International Affairs, 19, 55–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Räikkä, J. (1998). The feasibility condition in political theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 1, 27–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Southwood, N. (2008). Vindicating the normativity of rationality. Ethics, 119, 9–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Southwood, N. (2015a). Democracy as a modally demanding value. Noûs, 49, 504–521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Southwood, N. (2015b). The relevance of human nature. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.Google Scholar
  31. Southwood, N. (2016). “The Thing to Do” Implies “Can”. Noûs, 50, 61–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Southwood, N. (Ms). Does ‘Ought’ Imply ‘Feasible’? unpublished paper.Google Scholar
  33. Vihvelin, K. (2013). The philosophy of free will. In P. Russell & O. Deery (Eds.), Free will demystified: A dispositional account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Wiens, D. (2013). Demands of justice, feasible alternatives, and the need for causal analysis. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16, 325–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Wiens, D. (2015). Political ideals and the feasibility frontier. Economics and Philosophy, 31, 447–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Wiens, D. (2016). Motivational Limitations and the Demands of Justice. European Journal of Political Theory.Google Scholar
  37. Ypi, L. (2012). Global justice and avant-garde political agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Australian National UniversityCanberraAustralia
  2. 2.University of California San DiegoSan DiegoUSA

Personalised recommendations