Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 172, Issue 10, pp 2777–2798 | Cite as

Performance, self-explanation, and agency

  • Ron MallonEmail author
Article

Abstract

Social constructionist explanations of human thought and behavior hold that our representations (e.g. of race, or gender, or mental illness, or emotion) produce and regulate the categories, thoughts, and behaviors of those they represent. Performative versions of constructionist accounts explain these thoughts and behaviors as part of an intentional, strategic performance that is elicited and regulated by our representations of ourselves. This paper has four aims. First, I sketch a causal model of performative social constructionist claims. Second, I articulate a puzzling feature of performative claims that makes them seem especially implausible: the puzzle of intention and ignorance. Like other constructionists, performative constructionists are especially interested in explaining thoughts and behaviors that are widely but mistakenly believed to be the unintentional consequences of membership in a natural kind. But why doesn’t the intentional performance of a category undermine this ignorance? My third aim is to resolve this puzzle. I suggest that a plausible understanding can be found in the failure to locate one’s mental states in a causal explanation of one’s thoughts and actions. Finally, I argue that this model implies that the sorts of theories we (as a community or as a culture) offer of particular behaviors can create or destroy agency and responsibility with regard to those behaviors.

Keywords

Social construction Race Gender Self-knowledge Agency Responsibility Performance Performativity 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Research and writing of this paper was supported by the Princeton University Center for Human Values and the American Council of Learned Societies. I am grateful to Chrisoula Andreou, John Doris, Anne Eaton, Aaron Meskin, Shaun Nichols, Philip Pettit, Anya Plutynksi, and Stephen Stich, and audiences at Arizona, Arizona State, Duke, Houston, Princeton, Tulane, Washington University in St. Louis and Western Michigan for helpful discussion or comments on earlier drafts.

References

  1. American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5. Washington, DC: American Psychatric Publishing.Google Scholar
  2. American Psychiatric Association Ed. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV. Washington, DC: American Psychatric Publishing.Google Scholar
  3. Appiah, K. A. (1996). Race, culture, identity: Misunderstood connections. In K. A. Appiah & A. Guttmann (Eds.), Color conscious: The political morality of race. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Appiah, A. (2005). The ethics of identity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Averill, J. (1980a). A constructivist view of emotion. In R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman (Eds.), Emotion: Theory, research and experience: Theories of emotion (Vol. 1). New York City: Random House.Google Scholar
  6. Averill, J. (1980b). Emotion and anxiety: Sociocultural, biological, and psychological determinants. In A. Rorty (Ed.), Explaining emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  7. Brandon, R. N. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Castleman, M. (2009). Marital infidelity: How common is it?” All about sex blog. Retrieved March 6, 2014, from http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/all-about-sex/200910/marital-infidelity-how-common-is-it
  10. Doris, J. M. (2009). Skepticism about persons. Philosophical Issues, 19(1), 57–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Doris, J. (2015). Talking to our selves: Reflection, skepticism, and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  12. Eshleman, A. S. (2001). Being is not believing: Fischer and Ravizza on taking responsibility. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79(4), 479–490.Google Scholar
  13. Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.Google Scholar
  15. Ginet, C. (2006). Working with Fischer and Ravizza's account of moral responsibility. The Journal of Ethics, 10, 229–253.Google Scholar
  16. Goffman, E. (1970). Asylums: Essays on the social situation of mental patients and other inmates. Chicago: Aldine Pub. Co.Google Scholar
  17. Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really are: The problem of psychological categories. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hacking, I. (1986). Making up people. In T. C. Heller, M. Sosna, & D. E. Wellbery (Eds.), Reconstructing individualism: Autonomy, individuality, and the self in western thought (pp. 222–236). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Hacking, I. (1991). The making and molding of child abuse. Critical Inquiry, 17, 253–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hacking, I. (1992). World making by kind making: Child-abuse for example. In M. Douglas & D. Hull (Eds.), How classification works: Nelson Goodman among the social sciences (pp. 180–238). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hacking, I. (1995a). Rewriting the soul: Multiple personality and the sciences of memory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Hacking, I. (1995b). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 351–394). New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  23. Hacking, I. (1998). Mad travelers: Reflections on the reality of transient mental illnesses. Charlottesville, VA: University Press of Virginia.Google Scholar
  24. Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what?. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Hacking, I. (2005). Why race still matters. Daedelus, 134, 102–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Haslanger, S. (2003). Social construction: The “debunking” project. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics: The nature of social reality (pp. 301–325). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  28. Haslanger, S. A. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Isaacson. (2001). The heart wants what it wants. Time. http://content.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,160439,00.html. Accessed 6 March 2014.
  30. Kukla, A. (2000). Social constructivism and the philosophy of science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  31. Kunda, Z. (1999). Social cognition: Making sense of people. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  32. Levy, A. (2009). Nora Ephron knows what to do. New Yorker. 60–69. New York: Conde Nast.Google Scholar
  33. Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. New Castle: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  34. MacKinnon, C. A. (1987). Feminism unmodified: Discourses on life and law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  35. MacKinnon, C. A. (1989). Toward a feminist theory of the state. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Mallon, R. (2003). Social construction, social roles and stability. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics (pp. 327–353). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  37. Mallon, R. (2007). A field guide to social construction. Philosophy Compass, 2(1), 93–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. McKenna, M. (2000). Assessing reasons-responsive compatibilism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 8(1), 89–114.Google Scholar
  39. Monterosso, J., Royzman, E. B., et al. (2005). Explaining away responsibility: Effects of scientific explanation on perceived culpability. Ethics and Behavior, 15(2), 139–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Mottola, G. (2009). Adventureland, Miramax.Google Scholar
  41. Nahmias, E. (2007). Autonomous agency and the threat of social psychology. In M. Marraffa, M. Caro, & F. Ferretti (Eds.), Cartographies of the mind: Philosophy and psychology in intersection. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  42. Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Nisbett, R. E., & Bellows, N. (1977). Verbal reports about causal influences on social judgments: Private access vs. public theories. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35, 613–624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Nolan, J. M., Schultz, P. W., et al. (2008). Normative social influence is underdetected. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34(7), 913–923.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Pinker, S. (2002). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
  47. Robbins, P. (2006). The ins and outs of introspection. Philosophy Compass, 1(6), 617–630.Google Scholar
  48. Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology. New York: Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
  49. Scheff, T. J. (1974). The labelling theory of mental illness. American Sociological Review, 39, 444–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Shackelford, T. K., & Buss, D. M. (1996). Betrayal in mateships, friendships, and coalitions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22(11), 1151–1164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Taylor, C. (1976). Responsibility for self. In A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons (pp. 281–299). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  53. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind (pp. 19–136). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Trivers, R. (1976). Foreword. In R. Dawkins (Ed.), The selfish gene (pp. v–vii). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Velleman, J. D. (2000). The possibility of practical reason. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Vohs, K., & Schooler, J. W. (2008). The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science, 19(1), 49–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. von Hippel, W., & Trivers, R. (2011). The evolution and psychology of self deception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 1–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Weiner, B., Perry, R. P., et al. (1988). An attributional analysis of reactions to stigma. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55, 738–748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Wollstonecraft, M. (1995). A vindication of the rights of woman. In S. Tomaselli (Ed.), A vindication of the rights of man with a vindication of the rights of woman and hints (pp. 65–294). New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Woolfolk, R. L., Doris, J. M., & Darley, J. M. (2006). Identification, situational constraint, and social cognition: Studies in the attribution of moral responsibility. Cognition, 100(2), 283–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy and Philosophy-Neuroscience-Psychology ProgramWashington University in St. LouisSt. LouisUSA

Personalised recommendations