Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 169, Issue 3, pp 447–466 | Cite as

Being moved

  • Florian CovaEmail author
  • Julien A. Deonna
Article

Abstract

In this paper, we argue that, barring a few important exceptions, the phenomenon we refer to using the expression “being moved” is a distinct type of emotion. In this paper’s first section, we motivate this hypothesis by reflecting on our linguistic use of this expression. In section two, pursuing a methodology that is both conceptual and empirical, we try to show that the phenomenon satisfies the five most commonly used criteria in philosophy and psychology for thinking that some affective episode is a distinct emotion. Indeed, being moved, we claim, is the experience of a positive core value (particular object) perceived by the moved subject as standing out (formal object) in the circumstances triggering the emotion. Drawing on numerous examples, we describe the distinctively rich phenomenology characteristic of the experience as well as the far-reaching action-tendencies and functions associated with it. Having thus shown that the candidate emotion seem to satisfy the five criteria, we go on, in section three, to compare it with sadness and joy, arguing that it should not be confused with either. Finally, in section four, we illustrate the explanatory power of our account of “being moved” by showing how it can shed light on, and maybe even justify, the widespread distrust we feel towards the exhibition of ‘sentimentality’. On the whole and if we are right, we have uncovered an emotion which, though never or rarely talked about, is of great interest and no small importance.

Keywords

Being moved Emotions Sentimentality Values 

Notes

Acknowledgments

For their comments and suggestions on previous versions of the present paper, or help in its preparation, we would like to thank Constant Bonard, Otto Bruun, Tom Cochrane, Emma Dayer-Tieffenbach, Amanda Garcia, Jerrold Levinson, Patrizia Lombardo, Olivier Massin, Clare MacCumhail, Winfried Menninghaus, Agnes Moors, Kevin Mulligan, Hichem Naar, Isabelle Pitteloud, Vanessa Sennwald, Cristina Soriano, Fabrice Teroni, two anonymous reviewers, and the Swiss Centre for Affective Sciences.

References

  1. Claparède, E. (1928). Feeling and emotions. In M. L. Reymert (Ed.), Feelings and emotions. Worcester: Clark University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Claparède, E. (1930). L’émotion “pure”. Archives de Psychologie, 22, 333–347.Google Scholar
  3. Cova, F., Deonna, J., & Sander, D. (in preparation). Is elevation just a way of being moved?Google Scholar
  4. de Sousa, R. (1987). The rationality of emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Deonna, J. (2011). Etre ému. In C. Tappolet, F. Teroni, & A. Konzelmann Ziv (Eds.), Les Ombres de l’Âme: Penser les emotions negatives. Genève: Markus Haller.Google Scholar
  6. Deonna, J., Rodogno, R., & Teroni, F. (2011). In defense of shame: The faces of an emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Deonna, J., & Scherer, K. (2010). The case of the disappearing intentional object: Constraints on a definition of emotion. Emotion Review, 2, 44–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Deonna, J., & Teroni, F. (2012). The emotions: A philosophical introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Djikic, M., Oatley, K., Zoeterman, S., & Peterson, J. B. (2009). On being moved by art: How reading fiction transforms the self. Creativity Research Journal, 21, 24–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Fessler, D. M. T. (2004). Shame in two cultures: Implications for evolutionary approaches. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 4, 207–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fredrickson, B. L. (2001). The role of positive emotions in positive psychology: The broaden-and-build theory of positive emotions. American Psychologist, 56, 218–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fredrickson, B. L. (2009). Joy. In D. Sander & K. Scherer (Eds.), The Oxford companion to emotion and the affective sciences. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Frijda, N. (2007). The laws of emotion. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  14. Helm, B. (2009). Emotions as evaluative feelings. Emotion Review, 1, 248–255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Jefferson, M. (1983). What is wrong with sentimentality? Mind, 92, 519–529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Konecni, V. (2005). The aesthetic trinity: Awe, being moved, thrills. Bulletin of Psychology and the Arts, 5, 27–44.Google Scholar
  17. Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Emotion and adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Levinson, J. (2006). Musical chills. In Contemplating art: Essays in aesthetics. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
  19. Maslow, A. H. (1943). A theory of human motivation. Psychological Review, 50, 370–396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Panksepp, J. (1995). The emotional sources of “chills” induced by music. Music Perception, 13, 171–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Peterson, M. (1976–1977). Sentimentality. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Vol. 77, pp. 127–147).Google Scholar
  22. Rottenberg, J., & Vingerhoets, A. (2012). Crying: Call for a lifespan approach. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 6, 217–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Solomon, R. C. (1990). In defense of sentimentality. Philosophy and Literature, 14, 304–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Teroni, F. (2007). Emotions and formal object. Dialectica, 61, 395–415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Tetlock, P., Kristel, O., Elson, B., Green, M., & Lerner, J. (2000). The psychology of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbidden base-rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 853–870.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Vingerhoets, A. (2013). Why only humans weep: Unraveling the mysteries of tears. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Swiss Centre for Affective SciencesUniversity of GenevaGenevaSwitzerland

Personalised recommendations