Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 164, Issue 1, pp 163–187 | Cite as

Grounding practical normativity: going hybrid

  • Ruth ChangEmail author
Article

In virtue of what is something a reason for an agent to perform some action? In other words, what makes a consideration a reason for an agent to act?

This is a prima facie metaphysical or meta-normative question about the grounding of reasons for action and not a normative question about the circumstances or conditions under which, normatively speaking, one has a reason to do something. The normative question is answered by normative theory, as when one says that such-and-such feature of an action is a reason to perform that action because bringing about that feature would maximize happiness. The metaphysical question asks instead for the metaphysical determinant of something’s being a reason. When we ask for the ground of a reason’s normativity, we ask what metaphysically makes something have the action-guidingness of a reason: where does the normativity of a practical reason come from? As Christine Korsgaard puts it somewhat more poetically what is the ‘source’ of a reason’s...

Keywords

Normative Fact Hard Case Moral Fact Reason Problem Normative Source 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Kate Manne and Julia Markovitz for excellent commentary at the Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference where this paper was presented, and to the audience at the conference for a hybrid of entertaining and probing questions. Thanks are also due to Mary Clayton Coleman, Adam Elga, Kit Fine, Zachary Irving, Andrew Israelsen, Patrick Kain, Karin Nisenbaum, Derek Parfit, Juan Pineros, Luke Roelofs, Tina Rulli, and Jessica Wilson for useful discussion and more generally to audiences at the University of Toronto, the Murphy Institute at Tulane, and Purdue for useful feedback.

References

  1. Antosh, M. Rutgers, Ph.D. dissertation. Draft (Manuscript).Google Scholar
  2. Chang, R. (2002). The possibility of parity. Ethics, 112, 659–688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Chang, R. (2009). Voluntarist reasons and the sources of normativity. In Sobel & Wall (Eds.), Practical Reason and Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Chang, R. (2012). Are hard choices cases of incomparability? Philosophical Issues, 22(1), 106–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Chang, R. (2013a). Commitment, reasons, and the will, Oxford Studies in Metaethics 8.Google Scholar
  6. Chang, R. (2013b). Practical reasons: The problem of gridlock. In B. Dainton & H. Robinson (Eds.), Companion to Analytical Philosophy. New York: Continuum Press.Google Scholar
  7. Chang, R. Do We Have Normative Powers? Draft, (Manuscript).Google Scholar
  8. Clarke, S. (1706/1969). Discourse Concerning the Unchangeable Obligations of Natural Religion, and the Truth and Certainty of the Christian Revelation. In D.D. Raphael (Ed.), British Moralists: 1650-1800 (Vol. 1, pp. 224–261). Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  9. Coleman, M. C. Exploring Meta-Normative Constitutivism, (Manuscript).Google Scholar
  10. Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Enoch, D. (2006). Agency, Shmagency: Why normativity won’t come from what is constitutive of agency. Philosophical Review, 115, 169–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Enoch, D. (2011). Giving practical reasons. Philosophers’ Imprint, 11(4), 1–21.Google Scholar
  13. Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1(1), 1–30. Google Scholar
  14. Fitzpatrick, W. (2005). The practical turn in ethical theory: Korsgaard’s constructivism, realism, and the nature of normativity. Ethics, 115(4), 651–691.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hill, Thomas. (1991). Autonomy and self-respect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Koch, F. (2012). Voluntarism and Reflection. Ph.D Dissertation, Columbia.Google Scholar
  17. Kolodny, N. (2005). Why be rational? Mind, 114, 509–563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Korsgaard, C. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Korsgaard, C. (2003). Realism and constructivism in 20th century moral philosophy. Journal of Philosophical Research, 28, 99–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Korsgaard, C. (2008). The constitution of agency: Essays on practical reason and moral psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. MacCormick, N. (1972). Voluntary obligations and normative powers. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. 46, 59–78.Google Scholar
  23. Manne, K. How desires might matter: The veto power view. Draft, (Manuscript).Google Scholar
  24. Markovits, J. (2013). Moral reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Nichols, S. (2007). Sentimental rules. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Parfit, D. On How to Avoid the Repugnant Conclusion, Draft, (Manuscript).Google Scholar
  28. Railton, P. (2004). How to engage reason: The problem of regress. In Wallace et al. (Eds.), Reasons and values: Themes from the philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Railton, P. (Eds.). Toward a Unified Account of Rational Belief and Desire, Forthcoming (Manuscript).Google Scholar
  30. Raz, J. (1972). Voluntary obligations and normative powers. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. 46, 79–102.Google Scholar
  31. Raz, J. (1975). Practical reason and norms. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  32. Raz, J. (1999). Engaging reason: On the theory of value and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Raz, J. (2005). The myth of instrumental rationality. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 1(1), 1–28.Google Scholar
  34. Raz, J. (2011). From normativity to responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic & epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson & Company.Google Scholar
  37. Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
  38. Scanlon, T. (2003). Metaphysics and morals. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 77, 7–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Scanlon, T. (2004). Reasons: A puzzling duality? In Wallace, et al. (Eds.), Reason and Value: Themes form the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (pp. 231–246). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  40. Schneewind, J. (1998). The invention of autonomy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Shafir, E., Simonson, I., & Tversky, A. (1993). Reason-based choice. Cognition, 49, 11–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Street, S. (2009). In defense of future tuesday indifference: Ideally coherent eccentrics and the contingency of what matters. Philosophical Issues, 19, 273–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Thomson, J. J. (2008). Normativity. New York: Open Court.Google Scholar
  44. Tiberius, V. (2000). Humean heroism: Value commitments and the source of normativity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 18(4), 426–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Tiberius, V. (2008). The reflective life: Living wisely with our limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Verbeek, B. A Limited Vindication of Voluntarism in Practical Reason, (Manuscript).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyRutgers UniversityNew BrunswickUSA

Personalised recommendations