Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 160, Issue 1, pp 139–166 | Cite as

Interventionist counterfactuals

  • Rachael BriggsEmail author
Article

Abstract

A number of recent authors (Galles and Pearl, Found Sci 3 (1):151–182, 1998; Hiddleston, Noûs 39 (4):232–257, 2005; Halpern, J Artif Intell Res 12:317–337, 2000) advocate a causal modeling semantics for counterfactuals. But the precise logical significance of the causal modeling semantics remains murky. Particularly important, yet particularly under-explored, is its relationship to the similarity-based semantics for counterfactuals developed by Lewis (Counterfactuals. Harvard University Press, 1973b). The causal modeling semantics is both an account of the truth conditions of counterfactuals, and an account of which inferences involving counterfactuals are valid. As an account of truth conditions, it is incomplete. While Lewis’s similarity semantics lets us evaluate counterfactuals with arbitrarily complex antecedents and consequents, the causal modeling semantics makes it hard to ascertain the truth conditions of all but a highly restricted class of counterfactuals. I explain how to extend the causal modeling language to encompass a wider range of sentences, and provide a sound and complete axiomatization for the extended language. Extending the truth conditions for counterfactuals has serious consequences concerning valid inference. The extended language is unlike any logic of Lewis’s: modus ponens is invalid, and classical logical equivalents cannot be freely substituted in the antecedents of conditionals.

Keywords

Counterfactuals Causal modeling Modus ponens Simplification of disjunctive antecedents 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am thankful for the helpful questions and comments of audience members at the 2011 Carolina Metaphysics Workshop, the 2010 Formal Epistemology Workshop, and various workshops and departmental seminars in Australia. Special thanks are due to Delia Graff Fara and Peter Menzies for extensive commentary and discussion.

References

  1. Edgington, D. (2004). Counterfactuals and the benefit of hindsight. In: P. Dowe & P. Noordhof (Eds.), Cause and chance: Causation in an indeterministic world. Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Elga, A. (2001). Statistical mechanics and the asymmetry of counterfactual dependence. Philosophy of Science, 68S, S313–S324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Fine, K. (1975). Critical notice. Mind, 84(1), 451–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Fine, K. (forthcoming). Counterfactuals without possible worlds. The Journal of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  5. Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences, or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese, 28, 97–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Galles, D., & Pearl, J. (1998). An axiomatic characterization of causal counterfactuals. Foundations of Science, 3(1), 151–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Gundersen, L. B. (2004). Outline of a new semantics for counterfactuals. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85(1), 1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Hall, N. (2007). Structural equations and causation. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 109–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Halpern, J. (2000). Axiomatizing causal reasoning. Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, 12, 317–337.Google Scholar
  10. Handfield, T., Twardy, C. R., Korb, K. B., & Oppy, G. (2008). The metaphysics of causal models: Where’s the biff? Erkenntnis, 68(2), 149–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hawthorne, J. (2005) Chance and counterfactuals. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 396–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Hiddleston, E. (2005). A causal theory of counterfactuals. Noûs, 39(4), 232–257.Google Scholar
  13. Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in arrows and graphs. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(6), 273–299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hüber, F. Structural equations and beyond. manuscript.Google Scholar
  15. Kment, B. (2006). Counterfactuals and explanation. Mind, 115(458), 261–310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Krasner, D., & Heller, M. (1994). The miracle of counterfactuals: Counterexamples to lewis’s world ordering. Philosophical Studies, 76(1), 27–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lewis, D. (1973a). Causation. The Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lewis, D. K. (1973b). Counterfactuals. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Lewis, D. (1979) Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Lewis, D. (1981). Counterfactuals and comparative possibility. In W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.), Ifs, volume 15 of The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science (pp. 57–85). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  21. Lewis, D. (1986a). Introduction. In: Philosophical papers: Volume II. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Lewis, D. (1986b). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In Philosophical papers (Vol. II). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Loewer, B. (1976). Counterfactuals with disjunctive antecedents. The Journal of Philosophy, 73(16), 531–537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. McGee, V. (1985). A counterexample to modus ponens. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(9), 462–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Menzies, P. (2004). Causal models, token causation, and processes. Philosophy of Science, 71(5):820–832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Nute, D. (1978). Simplification and substitution of counterfactual antecedents. Philosophia, 7(2), 317–325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Penczek, A. (1997). Counterfactuals with true components. Erkenntnis, 46(1), 79–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sartorio, C. (2006). Disjunctive causes. Journal of Philosophy, 103 Google Scholar
  31. Schaffer, J. (2004). Counterfactuals, causal independence and conceptual circularity. Logic and Analysis, 64(4), 299–308.Google Scholar
  32. Stalnaker, R. (1981a). A defense of conditional excluded middle. In W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.), Ifs, volume 15 of The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science (pp. 87–104). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  33. Stalnaker, R. (1981b). A theory of conditionals. In W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.), Ifs, volume 15 of The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science (pp. 41–55). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  34. Wasserman, R. (2006). The future similarity objection revisited. Synthese, 150(1), 57–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part I: A counterfactual account. Noûs, 37(1), 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Australian National UniversityCanberraAustralia
  2. 2.Griffith UniversityNathanAustralia

Personalised recommendations