Philosophical Studies

, Volume 158, Issue 2, pp 313–342

Discourse dynamics, pragmatics, and indefinites

Article

References

  1. Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2003). Logics of conversation. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bratman, M. (1990). What is intention? In intentions in communication. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. Crimmins, M. (1992). Talk about beliefs. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Davis, W. A. (1998). Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of gricean theory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Dekker, P. (2004). Grounding dynamic semantics. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuiden- hout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Evans, G. (1977). Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(3), 467–536.Google Scholar
  7. Farkas, D. (2002). Varieties of indefinites. In: Proceedings of SALT 12.Google Scholar
  8. Grice, P. (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1990) Two theories of dynamic semantics. In Lecture Notes in Computer Science.Google Scholar
  10. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14, 39–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1999) Meaning in motion. In: K. von Huesinger & U. Egli (Eds.), Reference and anaphoric relations (pp. 47–76). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  12. Grosz, B., & Sidner, C. (1990). Plans for discourse. In: Intentions in communication (pp. 417–444). MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Harnish, R. (1976). Logical form and implicature. In J. J. Katz, T. G. Bever, & T. Langedoen (Eds.), An integrated theory of liguistic ability. Thomas Y. Crowell.Google Scholar
  14. Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. University of Massachusetts Dissertation.Google Scholar
  15. Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In Formal methods in the study of language, Mathematisch Centrum.Google Scholar
  16. Kamp, H. (1988) Comments on stalnaker, belief attribution and context. In Contents of thought. University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
  17. Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  18. King, J. (1994). Anaphora and operators. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 221–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. King, J. (2007). The nature and structure of content. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Krifka, M. (2001). Non-novel indefinites in adverbial quantification. In C. Condoravdi, & G. R. der Lavalette (Eds.), Logical perspec- tives on language and information, stanford. CSLI Press.Google Scholar
  21. Leech, G. (1983). Principles of pragmatics. Longmans.Google Scholar
  22. Levinson, S. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of general- ized conversational implicature. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philo- sophical Logic, 8(3), 339–359.Google Scholar
  25. Lewis, K. (2011). Understanding dynamic discourse. Rutgers University Dissertation.Google Scholar
  26. Litman, D. & Allen, J. (1990). Discourse processing and commonsense plans. In Intentions in communication. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  27. Muskens, R. (1996). Combining montague semantics and discourse representation. Linguistics and Philosophy, 19, 143–186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  29. Roberts, C. (2003). Uniqueness in definite noun phrases. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 287–350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Roberts, C. (ms). Retrievability and incomplete descriptions.Google Scholar
  31. Rooth, M. (1995). Indefinites, adverbs of quantification and focus seman- tics. In G. N. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book. Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and Semantics, 9.Google Scholar
  33. Stalnaker, R. (1998). On the representation of context. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 7, 3–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Szabo, Z. (2000). Descriptions and uniqueness. Philosophical Studies, 101, 29–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Thomason, R. (1990). Accommodation, meaning, and implicature: Interdisciplinary foundations for pragmatics. In P. R. Cohen, J. Morgan & M. E. Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. von Fintel, K. (1994). Restrictions on quantifier domains. University of Massachusetts at Amherst Dissertation.Google Scholar
  37. von Fintel, K., & Gillies, T. (2008). CIA leaks. Philosophical Review, 117, 77–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of Southern CaliforniaLos AngelesUSA

Personalised recommendations