Philosophical Studies

, Volume 164, Issue 3, pp 705–726 | Cite as

Ramseyan Humility, scepticism and grasp

Article

Abstract

In ‘Ramseyan Humility’ David Lewis argues that a particular view about fundamental properties, quidditism, leads to the position that we are irredeemably ignorant of the identities of fundamental properties. We are ignorant of the identities of fundamental properties since we can never know which properties play which causal roles, and we have no other way of identifying fundamental properties other than by the causal roles they play. It has been suggested in the philosophical literature that Lewis’ argument for Humility is merely an instance of traditional scepticism, to which traditional responses to scepticism are applicable. I agree that in ‘Ramseyan Humility’ Lewis does present an argument to which it is appropriate to consider the applicability of responses to traditional scepticism—he argues that we irredeemably lack the evidence to rule out possibilities in which different properties occupy the causal roles described by our best physical theory. And prima facie this is just the kind of argument responses to traditional scepticism are designed to tackle. However, I will argue that Lewis bolsters this argument with a second. This second argument serves to deepen Lewis’ case and cannot be met with a response to traditional scepticism. For Lewis argues that not only do we lack evidence for which properties play which roles, we lack the ability to grasp any such proposition about role-occupancy. And if we cannot grasp any such proposition we cannot know it.

Keywords

David Lewis Quidditism Ramseyan Humility Scepticism Humility Grasp 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Bill Brewer and Guy Longworth for very helpful discussions and for comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing this point, and for other helpful comments and challenges throughout.

References

  1. Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Chalmers, D. (2002). On sense and intension. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, 135–182.Google Scholar
  3. Chisholm, R. (1967). Identity through possible worlds: Some questions. Nous, 1(1), 1–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Hawthorne, J. (2006). Quantity in Lewisian metaphysics. In J. Hawthorne (Ed.), Metaphysical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Jackson, F. (2000). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Langton, R. (2004). Elusive knowledge of things in themselves. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82(1), 129–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Lewis, D. (1970). How to define theoretical terms. The Journal of Philosophy, 62(13), 427–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan Humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nold (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Locke, D. (2009). A partial defense of Ramseyan Humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nold (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Ney, A. (2007). Physicalism and out knowledge of intrinsic properties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(1), 41–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Schaffer, J. (2005). Quiddistic knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 123, 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Whittle, A. (2006). On an argument for humility. Philosophical Studies, 130(3), 461–497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.LondonUK

Personalised recommendations