Philosophical Studies

, Volume 166, Issue 2, pp 305–327

On non-pragmatic Millianism

Article

Abstract

Speakers often judge the sentence “Lois Lane believes that Superman flies” to be true and the sentence “Lois Lane believes that Clark Kent flies” to be false. If Millianism is true, however, these sentences express the very same proposition and must therefore have same truth value. “Pragmatic” Millians like Salmon and Soames have tried to explain speakers’ “anti-substitution intuitions” by claiming that the two sentences are routinely used to pragmatically convey different propositions which do have different truth values. “Non-Pragmatic” Millians like Braun, on the other hand, have argued that the Millian should not appeal to pragmatics and opt instead for a purely psychological explanation. I will present two objections against Non-Pragmatic Millianism. The first one is that the view cannot account for the intuitions of speakers who accept the identity sentence “Superman is Clark Kent”: applying a psychological account in this case, I will argue, would yield wrong predictions about speakers who resist substitution with simple sentences. I will then consider a possible response from the non-pragmatic Millian and show that the response would in fact require an appeal to pragmatics. My conclusion will be that Braun’s psychological explanation of anti-substitution intuitions is untenable, and that the Millian is therefore forced to adopt a pragmatic account. My second objection is that Non-Pragmatic Millianism cannot account for the role that certain commonsense intentional generalizations play in the explanation of behavior. I will consider a reply offered by Braun and argue that it still leaves out a large class of important generalizations. My conclusion will be that Braun’s non-pragmatic strategy fails, and that the Millian will again be forced to adopt a pragmatic account of intentional generalizations if he wants to respond to the objection. In light of my two objections, my general conclusion will be that non-pragmatic versions of Millianism should be rejected. This has an important consequence: if Millianism is true, then some pragmatic Millian account must be correct. It follows that, if standard objections against pragmatic accounts succeed, then Millianism must be rejected altogether.

Keywords

Millianism Pragmatics Psychological explanation Anti-substitution intuitions Intentional generalizations Ceteris paribus generalizations Explanation of behavior 

References

  1. Braun, D. (1998). Understanding belief reports. Philosophical Review, 107(4), 555–595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Braun, D. (2000). Russellianism and psychological generalizations. Nous, 34(2), 203–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Braun, D. (2001a). Russellianism and prediction. Philosophical Studies, 105(1), 59–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Braun, D. (2001b). Russellianism and explanation. Nous, 35(s15), 253–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Braun, D. (2006). Illogical, but rational. Noûs, 40(2), 376–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Braun, D., & Saul, J. (2002). Simple sentences, substitution, and mistaken evaluations. Philosophical Studies, 111(1), 1–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Braun, D., & Sider, T. (2006). Kripke’s revenge. Philosophical Studies, 128(3), 669–682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Crimmins, M., & Perry, J. (1989). The prince and the phone booth: reporting puzzling beliefs. Journal of Philosophy, 86(12), 685–711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Fodor, J. A. (1994). The elm and the expert. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Prinz, J. (2002). Furnishing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Richard, M. (1990). Propositional attitudes: An essay on thoughts and how we ascribe them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Richard, M. (1997). What does commonsense psychology tell us about meaning? Nous, 31(1), 87–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Salmon, N. (1986). Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Salmon, N. (1989). Illogical belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 243–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Salmon, N. (2006). The resilience of illogical belief. Noûs, 40(2), 369–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Saul, J. (1998). The pragmatics of attitude ascriptions. Philosophical Studies, 92(3), 363–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Schiffer, S. (1987). The ‘Fido’-Fido theory of belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 1, 455–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Schiffer, S. (1990). The mode-of-presentation problem. In C. Anderson & J. Owens (Eds.), Propositional attitudes. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar
  19. Schiffer, S. (2006). A problem for a direct-reference theory of belief reports. Noûs, 40(2), 361–368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Schneider, S. (2005). Direct reference, psychological explanation, and frege cases. Mind and Language, 20(4), 423–447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Soames, S. (1987). Substitutivity. In J. Thomson (Ed.), On being and saying (pp. 99–132). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Soames, S. (1995). Beyond singular propositions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 25(4), 515–549.Google Scholar
  23. Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyArché-Philosophical Research Centre, University of St. AndrewsSt. AndrewsUK

Personalised recommendations