Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 166, Issue 1, pp 109–121 | Cite as

Thinking animals, disagreement, and skepticism

  • Eric Yang
Article

Abstract

According to Eric Olson, the Thinking Animal Argument (TAA) is the best reason to accept animalism, the view that we are identical to animals. A novel criticism has been advanced against TAA, suggesting that it implicitly employs a dubious epistemological principle. I will argue that other epistemological principles can do the trick of saving the TAA, principles that appeal to recent issues regarding disagreement with peers and experts. I conclude with some remarks about the consequence of accepting these modified principles, drawing out some general morals in defending animalism.

Keywords

Animalism Persons Disagreement Live skepticism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for comments. I am especially indebted to Tony Brueckner for his helpful comments on an earlier draft and for our many discussions on these issues.

References

  1. Brueckner, A. (2006). Review of scepticism comes alive. Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 463–465.Google Scholar
  2. Brueckner, A., & Buford, C. (2009). Thinking animals and epistemology. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 90, 310–314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Dodd, D. (2007). Why Williamson should be a sceptic. Philosophical Quarterly, 57, 635–649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Dodd, D. (2011). Against fallibilism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 665–685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Feldman, R. (2006). Epistemological puzzles about disagreement. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology futures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Frances, B. (2005a). When a skeptical hypothesis is live. Nous, 39, 559–595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Frances, B. (2005b). Scepticism comes alive. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Frances, B. (2010). The reflective epistemic renegade. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 419–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Jehle, D., & Fitelson, B. (2009). What is the ‘Equal Weight View’? Episteme, 6, 280–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Kelly, T. (2005). The epistemic significance of disagreement, Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Lowe, E. J. (2010). Substance dualism: a non-Cartesian approach. In R. Koons & G. Bealer (Eds.), The waning of materialism (pp. 439–462). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Olson, E. (1997). The human animal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Olson, E. (2003). An argument for animalism. In R. Martin & J. Barresi (Eds.), Personal identity (pp. 318–334). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Olson, E. (2004). Animalism and the corpse problem. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 265–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Plantinga, A. (2007). Materialism and christian belief. In P. van Inwagen & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Persons: human and divine (pp. 99–141). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of California, Santa BarbaraSanta BarbaraUSA

Personalised recommendations