Philosophical Studies

, Volume 159, Issue 3, pp 457–465

Subjective consciousness and self-representation

Article

References

  1. Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown and Company.Google Scholar
  2. Hellie, B. (2007). Higher-order intentionality and higher-order acquaintance. Philosophical Studies, 134, 289–324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Hill, C. (2009). Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Kriegel, U. (2009). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Locke, J. (1690). An essay concerning human understanding. London: Thomas Ballet.Google Scholar
  7. Rosenthal, D. M. (1986). Two concepts of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 94, 329–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Rosenthal, D. M. (1997). A theory of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, & G. Guzeldere (Eds.), The nature of consciousness: Philosophical debates. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Van Gulick, R. (2003). Maps, gaps and traps. In A. Jokic & Q. Smith (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 323–352). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Van Gulick, R. (2004). HOGS (higher-order global states): an alternative higher-order model of consciousness. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness (pp. 67–92). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  11. Van Gulick, R. (2006). Mirror mirror, is that all? In U. Kriegel & K. Williford (Eds.), Self-representational approaches to consciousness (pp. 11–40). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophySyracuse UniversitySyracuseUSA

Personalised recommendations