Philosophical Studies

, Volume 161, Issue 3, pp 403–420 | Cite as

Soames’s argument 1 against strong two-dimensionalism

Article

Abstract

This paper criticizes Soames’s main argument against a variant of two-dimensionalism that he calls strong two-dimensionalism. The idea of Soames’s argument is to show that the strong two-dimensionalist’s semantics for belief ascriptions delivers wrong semantic verdicts about certain complex modal sentences that contain both such ascriptions and claims about the truth of the ascribed beliefs. A closer look at the formal semantics underlying strong two-dimensionalism reveals that there are two feasible ways of specifying the truth conditions for claims of the latter sort. Only one of the two yields the problematic semantic verdicts, so strong two-dimensionalists can avoid Soames’s argument by settling for the other way.

Keywords

Belief ascriptions Propositional attitude ascriptions Soames Two-dimensionalism Two-dimensional semantics 

References

  1. Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Chalmers, D. J. (2006). The foundations of two-dimensional semantics. In M. García-Carpintero, & M. Josep (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics (pp. 55–141). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Chalmers, D. J. (2011). Propositions and attitude ascriptions: A Fregean account. Noûs (forthcoming). http://consc.net/papers/propositions.pdf. Accessed date 28.7.2010.
  4. Cresswell, M. J. (1990). Entities and indices, studies in linguistics and philosophy (Vol. 41). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic PublishersGoogle Scholar
  5. Davies, M., & Humberstone, L. (1980). Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies, 38, 1–30Google Scholar
  6. Dever, J. (2007). Low grade two-dimensionalism. Philosophical Books, 48, 1–16Google Scholar
  7. Hofweber, T. (2005). A puzzle about ontology. Noûs, 39(2), 256–83Google Scholar
  8. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
  9. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  10. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
  11. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell PublishingGoogle Scholar
  12. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell PublishingGoogle Scholar
  13. Rayo, A., & Yablo, S. (2001). Nominalism through de-nominalization. Noûs, 35(1), 74–92Google Scholar
  14. Soames, S. (2005a). Reference and description. In F. Jackson, & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy (pp. 397–426). Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  15. Soames, S. (2005b). Reference and description: The case against two-dimensionalism. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
  16. Soames, S. (2006). Kripke, the necessary aposteriori, and the two-dimensionalist heresy. In M. Garcia-Carpintero, & M. Josep (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics (pp. 272–293). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Pragmatics, syntax and semantics (Vol. 9, pp. 315–332). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Département de philosophieeidos, Université de GenèveGenève 4Switzerland

Personalised recommendations