Philosophical Studies

, Volume 161, Issue 2, pp 287–308 | Cite as

How to refrain from answering Kripke’s puzzle

Article

Abstract

In this paper, I investigate the prospects for using the distinction between rejection and denial to resolve Saul Kripke’s puzzle about belief. One puzzle Kripke presents in “A Puzzle About Belief” poses what would have seemed a fairly straightforward question about the beliefs of the bilingual Pierre, who is disposed to sincerely and reflectively assent to the French sentence “Londres est jolie”, but not to the English sentence “London is pretty”, both of which he understands perfectly well. The question to be answered is whether Pierre believes that London is pretty, and Kripke argues, of each answer, that it is unacceptable. On my proposal, either answer to the question is to be rejected, but neither answer is to be denied, using the resource of partially-defined predicates. After demonstrating how this serves as a solution to the puzzle, I illustrate some philosophical motivations—independent of Kripke’s puzzle—for adopting a view on which belief is a partially defined predicate. I conclude that there are decent prospects for the proposed response to Kripke’s puzzle.

Keywords

Kripke’s puzzle Belief Dispositional account of belief Partially-defined predicates Rejection Denial Propositional attitudes Belief-ascriptions 

References

  1. Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, truth, and knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Atlas, J. (2004). Presupposition. In L. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  3. Bach, K. (1997). Do belief reports report beliefs? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 78(3), 215–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bealer, G. (1993). A solution to Frege’s puzzle. Philosophical Perspectives, 7, 17–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Crimmins, M. (1992). Talk about beliefs. Boston: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Crimmins, M., & Perry, J. (1989). The prince and the phone booth. The Journal of Philosophy, 86(12), 685–711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Fara, M. (2009). Dispositions. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer Edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/dispositions/.
  8. Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Fine, K. (2009). Semantic relationism. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  10. Forbes, G. (1990). Indispensability of sinn. The Philosophical Review, 99(4), 535–563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Frege, G. (1960). On sense and reference (orig. 1892) (Reprinted in Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing).Google Scholar
  12. Gunderson, L. (2002). In defense of the conditional account of dispositions. Synthese, 130(3), 389–411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 6(424), 641–660.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. King, J. (2001). Complex demonstratives. Boston: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 690–716.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kripke, S. (1979). A puzzle about belief. In A. Margalit (Ed.), Meaning and use. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.Google Scholar
  17. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Lewis, D. (1981). What puzzling Pierre does not believe. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59(3), 283–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Lewis, D. (2003). Finkish dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47(187), 143–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2008). On linking dispositions and conditionals. Mind, 117(465), 59–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. McGlone, M. (2007). Assertion, belief, and semantic content. Dissertation.Google Scholar
  22. Priest, G. (1987). In contradiction: A study of the transconsistent. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  23. Priest, G., & Berto, F. (2010). Dialetheism. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer Edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/dialetheism/.
  24. Richard, M. (1990). Propositional attitudes: An essay on thoughts and how we ascribe them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Salmon, N. (1989). Illogical belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 243–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Salmon, N. (2002). Demonstrating and necessity. The Philosophical Review, 111(4), 497–537.Google Scholar
  27. Schiffer, S. (1987). Belief ascription. The Journal of Philosophy, 89(10), 499–521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Nous, 36(2), 249–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Soames, S. (1999). Understanding truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Soames, S. (2004). Naming and asserting. In Z. Szabo (Ed.), Semantics and pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Soames, S. (2009). The possibility of partial definition. In R. Dietz & S. Moruzzi (Eds.), Cuts and clouds: Essays on the nature of vagueness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Stalnaker, R. (1999). Belief attribution and context. In R. Stalnaker (Ed.), Context and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Strawson, P. (1950). On Referring. Mind, 59(235), 320–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyWayne State UniversityDetroitUSA

Personalised recommendations