Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 136, Issue 1, pp 99–121 | Cite as

The contingency of composition

  • Ross P. Cameron
Article

Abstract

There is widespread disagreement as to what the facts are concerning just when a collection of objects composes some further object; but there is widespread agreement that, whatever those facts are, they are necessary. I am unhappy to simply assume this, and in this paper I ask whether there is reason to think that the facts concerning when composition occurs hold necessarily. I consider various reasons to think so, but find fault with each of them. I examine the theory of composition as identity, but argue that the version of this doctrine that entails universalism is unwarranted. I consider the claim that the a priority of such facts leads to their necessity, but give a defence of substantial contingent a priori truths. I ask whether the contingency of such facts would lead to unwelcome possibilities, but argue that it does not. Next, I argue against the thought that the Lewis–Sider argument against restricted composition might give us reason to accept the necessity of universalism. Lastly, I respond to two objections from the 2006 BSPC. I conclude in favour of the contingency of the facts concerning when some things compose some thing.

Keywords

Composition Modality 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Elizabeth Barnes, Bob Hale, Daniel Nolan and Robert Williams for helpful comments. Thanks also to participants at the 2006 BSPC conference at Western Washington University, especially Karen Bennett, Cody Gilmore, Ned Markosian and Ted Sider.

References

  1. Armstrong, David (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Armstrong, David (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Barnes, Elizabeth (2005). Vagueness in sparseness: A study in property ontology. Analysis, 65(4), 315–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Baxter, Donald (1988). Identity in the loose and popular sense. Mind, 97(388), 575–582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Baxter, Donald (1988). Many-one identity. Philosophical Papers, 17(3), 193–216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bigelow, John (1988). The reality of numbers: A physicalist’s philosophy of mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Blackburn, Simon (1984). Spreading the word. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  8. Donnellan, Keith (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Evans, Gareth (Ed.) (1985). Reference and contingency. In Collected papers (pp. 178–213). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  10. Hale, Bob (2003). Knowledge of possibility and necessity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, CIII(1), 1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kripke, Saul A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Vander Laan, David (2004). Counterpossibles and similarity. In Jackson Frank & Priest Graham (Eds.) Lewisian themes (pp. 258–275). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  13. Lewis, David (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Lewis, David (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Lewis, David (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  16. Lewis, David (2001). Truthmaking and difference-making. Nous, 35(4), 602–615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Markosian, Ned (1998). Brutal composition. Philosophical Studies, 92, 211–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Merricks, Trenton (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  19. Merricks, Trenton (2005). Composition and vagueness. Mind, 114, 615–637.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Nolan, Daniel (1997a). Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38(4), 535–572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Nolan, Daniel (1997b). Quantitative parsimony. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48, 329–343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Nolan, Daniel (2005). Daniel Lewis. Bucks: Acumen.Google Scholar
  23. Nolan, Daniel (2006). Vagueness, multiplicity and parts. Noûs, 40(4), 716–737.Google Scholar
  24. Robert, Stalnaker (Ed.) (1999a). Assertion. In Context and content (pp. 78–95). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Robert, Stalnaker (1999b). Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Robert, Stalnaker (Ed.) (1999c). Introduction to context and content. In Context and Content (pp. 1–28) Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Rosen, Gideon, & Dorr, Cian (2002). Composition as a fiction. In Gale, Richard M. (Ed.) ,The Blackwell guide to metaphysics (pp. 151–174). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  28. Sidelle, Alan (2002). Is there a true metaphysics of material objects? Philosophical Issues, 12, 118–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Sider, Theodore (1993). van Inwagen and the possibility of gunk. Analysis, 53, 285–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sider, Theodore (2001). Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Sider, Theodore (2003). Reductive theories of modality. In Loux, Michaelm J. & Zimmerman, Dean Wand (Eds.) The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 180– 208). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Sider, Theodore (2007). Parthood. The Philosophical Review, 116, 51–91.Google Scholar
  33. Simons, Peter (1987). Parts: A study in ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. van Inwagen, Peter (1990). Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  35. van Inwagen, Peter (1994). Composition as identity. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 204–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Yi, Byeong-Uk (1999). Is mereology ontologically innocent? Philosophical Studies, 93, 141–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of LeedsLeedsUK

Personalised recommendations