Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 128, Issue 1, pp 109–135 | Cite as

Inductive Incompleteness

  • Matthias HildEmail author
Article
  • 71 Downloads

Abstract

Nelson Goodman cast the ‘problem of induction’ as the task of articulating the principles and standards by which to distinguish valid from invalid inductive inferences. This paper explores some logical bounds on the ability of a rational reasoner to accomplish this task. By a simple argument, either an inductive inference method cannot admit its own fallibility, or there exists some non-inferable hypothesis whose non-inferability the method cannot infer (violating the principle of ‘negative introspection’). The paper discusses some implications of this limited self-knowledge for the justifiability of inductive inferences, auto-epistemic logic, and the epistemic foundations of game theory.

Keywords

Game Theory Inference Method Inductive Inference Simple Argument Rational Reasoner 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Arnauld, A. and Nicole, P. (1662): La Logique ou l’Art de Penser. Reprinted by P. Clair and F. Girbal (eds.), Presses Universitaire de France, Paris, 1965Google Scholar
  2. Aumann, R.J. 1976‘Agreeing to Disagree’Annals of Statistics412361239Google Scholar
  3. Bayes, T. (1764): A Method of Calculating the Exact Probability of All Conclusions Founded in Induction. Philosophical Transactions Google Scholar
  4. Bonanno, G., Nehring, K. 1998‘On the Logic and Role of Negative Introspection of Common Belief’Mathematical Social Sciences351736CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. 1950Logical Foundations of ProbabilityUniversity of Chicago PressChicagoGoogle Scholar
  6. Dawid, A.P. 1982‘The well-calibrated Bayesian’Journal of the American Statistical Association77605613CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Dawid, A.P. 1992‘Prequential Analysis, Stochastic Complexity and Bayesian Inference’Bernardo, J.M.Berger, J.O.Dawid, A.P.Smith, A.F.M. eds. Bayesian StatisticsOUPOxford109125Google Scholar
  8. de Finetti, B. (1931): ‘Probabilismo’, Logos 14, 163–219. (Translated by M.C. Di Maio, M.C. Galavotti, R.C. Jeffrey) in: ‘Probabilism’, Erkenntnis 31, 169–223Google Scholar
  9. Finetti, B. 1937‘La prévision: Ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives’Annales de l’Institut International de Statistique7168Google Scholar
  10. Descartes, R. (1641): Meditationes de Prima Philosophia. Reprinted in C. Adam and P. Tannery (eds.), Oeuvres de Descartes, Vrin, Paris, 1996Google Scholar
  11. Fitzgerald, W.D., Smith, R.L., Walden, A.T., Young, P.C. 2000Nonlinear and Nonstationary Signal ProcessingCUPCambridgeGoogle Scholar
  12. Gärdenfors, P. 1988Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic StatesMITCambridge (Mass.)Google Scholar
  13. Gelfond, M. (1987): On Stratified Autoepistemic Theories. Proceedings of AAAI–87, 207–211Google Scholar
  14. Gödel, K. 1931‘Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme’Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik38173198CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Goodman, N. 1955Fact, Fiction and ForecastN.NLondonGoogle Scholar
  16. Harman, G. 1965‘The inference to the best explanation’Philosophical Review748895CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Harman, G. 1968‘Enumerative Induction as Inference to the Best Explanation’Journal of Philosophy65529533CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Harsanyi, J. (1967–68): ‘Games with Incomplete Information Played by Bayesian Players, parts I–III’, Management Science 14, 159–182, 320–334, 486–502Google Scholar
  19. Hempel, C.G. 1960‘Inductive inconsistencies’Synthese12439469CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hilbert, D. 1922‘Neubegründung der Mathematik: Erste Mitteilung’Abhandlungen aus dem Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität1157177Google Scholar
  21. Hild, M., Jeffrey, R., Risse, M. 1998‘Agreeing to Disagree: Harsanyi and Aumann’Leinfellner, W.Köhler, E. eds. Game Theory, Experience, Rationality: Foundations of Social Sciences, Economics and Ehtics – In Honor of John C. HarsanyiKluwer AcademicDordrecht108115Google Scholar
  22. Hintikka, J. 1962Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two NotionsCornellIthaca (N.Y.)Google Scholar
  23. Hirth, R.A., Chernew, M.E., Miller, E., Fendrick, A.M., Weissert, W.G. 2000‘Willingness to pay for a quality-adjusted life year: In search of a standard’Medical Decision Making20332342Google Scholar
  24. Hume, D. (1748): Philosophical Essays Concerning Human Understanding. Reprinted in L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch (eds.), Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975Google Scholar
  25. Jeffrey, R.C. (2002): After Logical Empiricism. Colibri, Lisbon. (English edition with Portuguese translation by António Zilão)Google Scholar
  26. Jeffreys, H. 1939Theory of Probability3Clarendon PressOxford1961Google Scholar
  27. Keynes, J.M. 1921A Treatise on ProbabilityMacmillanLondonGoogle Scholar
  28. Konolige, K. 1988‘On the Relationship between Default and Autoepistemic logic’Artificial Intelligence35343382CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Laplace, P.S. 1812Theorie Analytique des ProbabilitésCourcierParisGoogle Scholar
  30. Levi, I. 1967Gambling with TruthKnopfNew YorkGoogle Scholar
  31. Levi, I. 1980The Enterprise of KnowledgeMITCambridge (Mass.)Google Scholar
  32. Lewis, D. 1969Convention: A Philosophical StudyHarvard UniversityCambridge (Mass.)Google Scholar
  33. Lewis, D. 1973CounterfactualsBlackwellOxfordGoogle Scholar
  34. Lipton, P. 1991Inference to the Best ExplanationRoutledgeLondonGoogle Scholar
  35. Makinson, D.C. 1965‘The Paradox of the Preface’Analysis25205207Google Scholar
  36. Moore, G.E. 1942‘A Reply to my Critics’Schlipp, P.A. eds. The Philosophy of G.E. Moore2TudorNew York5336771952Google Scholar
  37. Moore, R.C. 1985‘Semantic considerations on non-monotonic logic’Artificial Intelligence257594CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Morris, S. 1995‘The Common Prior Assumption in Economic Theory’Economics and Philosophy11227253CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Muggleton, S. eds. 1992Inductive Logic ProgrammingAcademic PressLondonGoogle Scholar
  40. Neyman, J., Pearson, E.S. 1967Joint Statistical PapersCUPCambridgeGoogle Scholar
  41. Popper, K.R. 1935Logik der ForschungMohrTübingenGoogle Scholar
  42. Quine, W.V.O., Ullian, J.S. 1970The Web of BeliefRandom HouseNew YorkGoogle Scholar
  43. Reiter, R. 1980‘A Logic for Default Reasoning’Artificial Intelligence1381132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Rescher, N. 1964Hypothetical ReasoningNorth–HollandAmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  45. Russell, B. (1902): Letter to Gottlob Frege. Reprinted in J. van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel, Harvard University, Cambridge (Mass.), 1967, 124–125Google Scholar
  46. Samet, D. 1990‘Ignoring Ignorance and Agreeing to Disagree’Journal of Economic Theory52190207CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Shapiro, E.Y. 1983Algorithmic Program DebuggingMITCambridge (Mass.)Google Scholar
  48. Stalnaker, R.C. (1980): A note on nonmonotonic modal logic. Technical report, Department of Philosophy, Cornell UniversityGoogle Scholar
  49. Teller, P. 1976‘Conditionalization, Observation, and Change of Preference’Harper, W.Hooker, C.A. eds. Foundations of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and Statistical Theories of Science.ReidelDordrecht205259Google Scholar
  50. Vapnik, V.N. 1998Statistical Learning TheoryWileyNew YorkGoogle Scholar
  51. Wald, A. 1950Statistical Decision FunctionsWileyNew YorkGoogle Scholar
  52. Yuan, L.Y. 1994‘Autoepistemic Logic of First order and its Expressive Power’Journal of Automated Reasoning136982CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Yuan, L.Y., You, J.I., Goebel, R. 1998‘Disjunctive Logic Programming and Autoepistemic logic’Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence147185101Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Darden Business SchoolCharlottesvilleUSA

Personalised recommendations