Advertisement

What is it like to think about oneself? De Se thought and phenomenal intentionality

  • Kyle Banick
Article
  • 44 Downloads

Abstract

The topic of the paper is at the intersection of recent debates on de se thought and phenomenal intentionality. An interesting problem for phenomenal intentionality is the question of how to account for the intentional properties of de se thought-contents---i.e., thoughts about oneself as oneself. Here, I aim to describe and consider the significance of a phenomenological perspective on self-consciousness in its application to de se thought. I argue that having de se thoughts can be explained in terms of the ways that subjects consciously attend to themselves in experiences of thinking. Therefore, a strong form of first-person persectivalness, in which the subject is capable of self-directed control of the focus of conscious attention, is required for de se thought. But no constraints on the semantic content of such thoughts are required. The outcome of the question therefore bears importantly on both on the problem of self-reflexive self-reference and the wider problem of self-consciousness. My model suggests phenomenologically-derived conceptual constraints for the extension of minimal, background forms of self-awareness to robust, cognitive forms of self-awareness that have been of interest in recent empirical studies on self-consciousness. The framework therefore provides a way of operationalizing the concept of self-reflexive consciousness by deploying widely deployed notions from the empirical literature such as attention and minimal phenomenal selfhood, enabling a framework for empirically falsifiable hypotheses about the neural mechanisms underlying the structure of self-consciousness. What Is it Like to Think about Oneself? De Se Thought and Phenomenal Intentionality.

Keywords

Phenomenal intentionality Self-consciousness De se semantics Cognitive phenomenology Pre-reflective self-consciousness 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank David Woodruff Smith and Sean Walsh for tireless discussions of cognitive phenomenology and de se semantics.An early version of this work was presented at the Rudolf-Carnap-Lectures at Ruhr-Universität Bochum, Germany in 2018. I am gratefulto the audience, and in particular to Thomas Metzinger, for their responses that shaped the final version. Finally, I would like to thank the anonymous referees for their insightful comments.

References

  1. Bayne, T., & Montague, M. (Eds.). (2011). Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Billon, A., & Kriegel, U. (2015). Jaspers’ dilemma: The psychopathological challenge to subjectivity theories of consciousness. In R. J. Gennaro (Ed.), Disturbed consciousness: New essays on psychopathology and theories of consciousness (pp. 29–54). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Blanke, O. (2013). Neuroscience of self-consciousness and subjectivity. Scripta Varia, 121.Google Scholar
  4. Blanke, O., & Metzinger, T. (2009). Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal self-hood. Trends in Cognitive Science, 13, 7–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brentano, F. (1874/2014). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Translated by Rancurello, Terrell, and McAlister. Routledge.Google Scholar
  6. Breyer, T., & Gutland, C. (Eds.). (2016). The phenomenology of thinking: Philosophical investigations into the character of cognitive experiences. Routledge.Google Scholar
  7. Cappelin, H., & Dever, J. (2013). The inessential indexical: On the philosophical insignificance of perspective and the first-person. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Campbell, J. (2011). Visual Attention and the Epistemic Role of Consciousness. In Christopher Mole, Declan Smithies & Wayne Wu (eds.), Attention: Philosophical and Psychological Essays. Oxford University Press, 323.Google Scholar
  10. Carruthers, P., & Veillet, B. (2011). The case against cognitive phenomenology. In Bayne, T. and Montague, M (pp. 35–56). Cognitive Phenomenology: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Castañeda, H. (1967). He’: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio, 8, 130–157.Google Scholar
  12. Craik, F. I. M., Moroz, T. M., Moscovitch, M., Stuss, D. T., Wincour, G., Tulving, E., & Kapur, S. (1999). In Search of the self: A positron emission tomography study. Psychological Science, 10, 26–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dickie, I. (2011). “Visual attention fixes demonstrative reference by eliminating referential luck.” In mole, smithies, and Wu, eds., Attention: Philosophical and Psychological Essays, 292–322. Oxford University press.Google Scholar
  14. Farkas, K. (2008). Phenomenal intentionality without compromise. The Monist, 91(2), 273–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Findlay, J., & Gilchrist, I. (2003). Active vision: The psychology of looking and seeing. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Ford, J. and Smith, D.W. (2006). Consciousness, self, and attention. In Kriegel and Williford, (eds.), Self-representational approaches to consciousness. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Frege, G. (1892/1918). Uber Sinn und Bedeutung. In Zeitschrift fur Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik, 100.Google Scholar
  18. Gallagher, S. (2000). Self-Reference and Schizophrenia: A Cognitive Model of Immunity to Error through Misidentification. In Zahavi (ed.), Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological Perspectives on Self-Experience. John Benjamins Publishing Company, 203–240.Google Scholar
  19. García-Carpintero, M. (2017). The philosophical significance of the De se. Inquiry, 60(3), 253–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Garcia-Carpintero, M. and Torre, S., Eds. (2016). About Oneself: De Se Thought and Communication. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Gibbard, A. (2012). Meaning and normativity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Gurwitsch, A. (1964). The Field of Consciousness. Pittsburgh: Duquesne. University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University press, pgs (pp. 520–533).Google Scholar
  24. Husserl, E. (1963). Ideas: A General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Trans. W. R. Boyce Gibson. New York: Collier Books. From the German original of 1913, originally titled Ideas pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1983.Google Scholar
  25. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes From Kaplan. Oxford University press (pp. 481–563).Google Scholar
  26. Kiverstein, J. (2010). Sensorimotor knowledge and the contents of experience. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, action, and consciousness: Sensorimotor dynamics and two visual systems (pp. 257–274). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Kriegel, U. (2011). The sources of intentionality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Leech, R., & Sharp, D. J. (2014). The role of the posterior cingulate cortex in cognition and disease. Brain, 137(1), 12–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness. (Vol. 6). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review, 88(4), 513–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Liu, J., & Perry, J. (Eds.). (2011). Consciousness and the self: New essays. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content, in Martin Hahn & B. Ramberg, eds., Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 229–258.Google Scholar
  33. Lou, H. C., Luber, B., Crupain, M., Keenan, J. P., Nowak, M., Kjaer, T. W., Sackeim, H. A., & Lisanby, S. H. (2004). Parietal cortex and representation of the mental self. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 101, 6827–6832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Lou, H. C., Changeux, J. P., & Rosenstand, A. (2016). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of self-awareness. In Neuroscience and behavioral reviews.Google Scholar
  35. Lycan, W. (2008). Phenomenal Intentionalities. American Philosophical Quarterly, 45, 233–252.Google Scholar
  36. Magidor, O. (2015). The myth of the De se. Philosophical Perspectives., 29(1), 249–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. McGinn, C. (1997). Consciousness and Content. In Block, Flanagan, Guezeldere, eds. The Nature of Consciousness, 295–307. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  38. Moss, Sarah. (2012). Updating as communication. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85, pg. 225–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Newen, A., & Vogeley, K. (2003). Self-representation: Searching for a neural signature of self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 12(2003), 529–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Ninan, D. (2010). De Se Attitudes. Philosophy Compass 5, pgs. 551–567.Google Scholar
  41. O’Brien, L. (2007). Self-knowing agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Peacocke, C. (1983). Sense and content. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  43. Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Perry, J. (1993). “Postscript to the problem of the essential indexical,” in his The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 50–52.Google Scholar
  45. Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition, or, what is it like to think that P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 1–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Pitt, D. (2011). Introspection, phenomenality and the availability of intentional content. In T. Bayne & M. Montague (Eds.), Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University press, pgs (pp. 141–173).Google Scholar
  47. Pitt, D. (2013). Indexical thought. In P. Intentionality (Ed.), Kriegel. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Smithies, D. (2011). What is the role of consciousness in demonstrative thought? Journal of Philosophy, 108(1), 5–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Stalnaker, R. (1981). Indexical Belief. Synthese, 49, 129–151.Google Scholar
  50. Thomasson, A. L. (2000). After Brentano: A one-level theory of consciousness. European Journal of Philosophy, 8(2), 190–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Torre, S. (2010). Centered assertion. Philosophical Studies, 150, 97–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Torre, S. (2016). De se thought and communication: an introduction. In Garcia-Carpintero and Torre, (eds.), About oneself: De se thought and Communication Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Tye, M., & Wright, B. (2011). Is there a phenomenology of thought? In T. Bayne & M. Montague (Eds.), Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University press, pgs (pp. 326–344).Google Scholar
  54. Weber, C. (2013). Centered communication. Philosophical Studies 166, pgs. 205–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Wu, W. (2014). Attention. Routledge.Google Scholar
  56. Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Zahavi, D., & Kriegel, U. (2015). For-me-ness: What it is and what it is not. In D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, & W. Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of mind and phenomenology (pp. 36–53). Routledge.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of CaliforniaIrvineUSA

Personalised recommendations