Advertisement

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 14, Issue 4, pp 673–682 | Cite as

The social roots of normativity

  • Glenda SatneEmail author
Article

Abstract

This paper introduces the Special Issue: ‘The Roots of Normativity. Developmental, Comparative and Conceptual issues’. The contributions collected in this volume aim to present a picture of contemporary accounts of normativity that integrate philosophy and developmental and comparative psychology and purport to provide the reader with new insights regarding a classical debate about what makes us human: being governed by norms and being able to orient ourselves in the light of them. This introduction presents a broad picture of the issues at the heart of traditional discussions on normativity and lays out a set of conditions which a proper account of normativity should meet. In so doing the main common themes that unify these papers are brought to the fore. In particular, all of them share the idea that human-specific norms are themselves social. Once questions concerning the evolution of normative capacities and their development are considered, however, they pose - so it is argued - specific challenges to an account of normativity. While the traditional approaches fail to face such challenges, it is the main aim of the papers in this Special Issue to meet them. In concluding, a brief overview of each paper is provided.

Keywords

Human normativity Social norms Development Non-human primates Normative behavior Phylogeny 

References

  1. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1978). Rules, Rights and Promises. Midwest Studies In Philosophy, 3(1), 318–323.Google Scholar
  2. Boghossian, P. (2005). Is Meaning Normative?” in Christian Nimtz and Ansgar Beckermann (eds.): Philosophy—Science—Scientific Philosophy. Main Lectures and Colloquia of GAP.5, Fifth International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, Bielefeld, 2003, Mentis.Google Scholar
  3. Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
  4. Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperative activity. The Philosophical Review, 101(2), 327–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brinck, I. (2015). Understanding social norms and constitutive rules: perspectives from developmental psychology and philosophy. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi: 10.1007/s11097-015-9426-y.
  6. Davidson, D. (1992). The Second Person. In Donald Davidson (2001), Subjective, Intersubjective and Objective. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
  7. Glüer, K., & Wirkfoss, A. (2009). Against content normativity. Mind, 118(469), 31–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Grice, P. (1957). Meaning. The Philosophical Review, 66, 377–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Grice, P. (1969). Utterer’s meaning and intentions. The Philosophical Review, 68, 147–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hume, D. (1752). Essays moral, political, literary, edited and with a Foreword, Notes, and Glossary by Eugene F. Miller, with an appendix of variant readings from the 1889 edition by T.H. Green and T.H. Grose, revised edition, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund 1987.Google Scholar
  11. Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
  12. Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
  13. McDowell, J. (1984). Wittgenstein on Following a Rule. Synthese, 58, 325–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Rakoczy, H., & Tomasello, M. (2007). The Ontogeny of Social Ontology: Steps to Shared Intentionality and Status Functions. In S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Intentional Acts and Institutional Facts: Essays on John Searle’s social ontology (pp. 113–137). Berlin: Springer Verlag.Google Scholar
  15. Rochat, P. (2015). Self-conscious roots of human normativity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi: 10.1007/s11097-015-9427-x.
  16. Rödl, S. (2007). Self-consciousness. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
  17. Rödl, S. (2014). Intentional transaction. Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action, 17(3), 304–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Satne, G. (2008). Normatividad sin reglas. In Conceptos, creencias y racionalidad. Córdoba: Brujas.Google Scholar
  19. Satne, G. (2015). What Binds Us Together. Normativity and the Second Person, Philosophical Topics, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  20. Searle, J. (1990). Collective Intentions and Actions. In P. Cohen et al. (Eds.), Intentions and Communication. Cambridge: Bradford.Google Scholar
  21. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations (abbreviation: PI), Eds. G.E.M. Anscombe & E. Rhees, transl. G.E.M. Anscombe, Blackwell, Oxford.Google Scholar
  22. Wittgenstein, L. (1983). Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. (abbreviation: RFM) Ed. by G. von Wright, G.E.M Anscombe, R. Rhees and G.E.M. Anscombe, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Wright, C. (2001). Rails to infinity. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
  24. Wright, C. (2002). What is Wittgenstein’s Point in the Rule-Following Discussion?” published online: www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/…/rules/…/Wright.pdf

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyAlberto Hurtado UniversitySantiagoChile
  2. 2.School of Humanities and Social InquiryUniversity of WollongongWollongongAustralia

Personalised recommendations