Advertisement

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 13, Issue 2, pp 241–256 | Cite as

Neural representations not needed - no more pleas, please

  • Daniel D. Hutto
  • Erik Myin
Article

Abstract

Colombo (Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2012) argues that we have compelling reasons to posit neural representations because doing so yields unique explanatory purchase in central cases of social norm compliance. We aim to show that there is no positive substance to Colombo’s plea—nothing that ought to move us to endorse representationalism in this domain, on any level. We point out that exposing the vices of the phenomenological arguments against representationalism does not, on its own, advance the case for representationalism one inch—beyond establishing its mere possibility. We criticize the continual confounding of constitutive and explanatory claims and the lack of recognition of a Hard Problem of having to provide a naturalistic account of content, coupled with an inability to face up to it. We point at the inadequacy of various deflationary moves that end up driving representationalists towards the idea of neural representations with non-standard contents or without content altogether, both of which either render neural representationalism unfit for purpose or vacuous. Referring to possibilities for neural manipulation and control, or to established scientific practice does not help representationalism either.

Keywords

Neural representation Mental representation Mental content Social norm compliance 

Notes

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by the Australian Research Council Discovery Project, “Embodied Virtues and Expertise” (DP: 1095109); the Marie-Curie Initial Training Network, “TESIS: Towards an Embodied Science of InterSubjectivity” (FP7-PEOPLE-2010-ITN, 264828); and the (Ministerio de Economía e innovación) Spanish Department of Economy and Innovation: “Agency, Normativity and Identity: the Presence of the Subject in Actions” (FFI-2011-25131).

Erik Myin is grateful to the Research Foundation Flanders for financial support (project “Computation reconsidered”, G0B5312N).

References

  1. Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society‬: The nature and dynamics of social norms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Block. (1986/1994). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest studies in philosophy X. Reprinted in Stich, S and Warfield, T.A. Mental representation: A reader (pp. 81-141). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  3. Burge, T. (2010). The origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Churchland, P. M. (2012). Plato’s camera: How the physical brain captures a landscape of abstract universals. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Colombo, M. (2012). Explaining social norm compliance. A plea for neural representations. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi: 10.1007/s11097-013-9296-0.
  8. Crane, T. (2009). Is perception a propositional attitude? The Philosophical Quarterly, 59, 452–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Currie, C. (2004). Arts and minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Froese, T., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2011). The enactive approach: theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics and Cognition, 19, 1–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gauker, C. (2011). Words and images. An essay on the origin of ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Hutto, D.D. (2008). Folk Psychological Narratives: The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Isaac, A. M. C. (2012). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. (pp. 1–22) (forthcomming).Google Scholar
  15. Kawato, M. (2007). From "Understanding the brain by creating the brain" toward Manipulative Neuroscience. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B.Google Scholar
  16. Myin, E., & Degenaar, J. (2013). Enactive vision. In L. Shapiro (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition. Oxford: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). What’s in your mind. In E. Lepore & Z. Pylyshyn (Eds.), What is cognitive science? (pp. 1–25). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Sato, H., and Maharbiz, M.M. (2010). Recent developments in the remote radio control of insect flight. Frontiers in NeuroscienceIm 4:199.Google Scholar
  20. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of the mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Warfield, T. A., & Stich, S. (1994). Introduction. In S. Stich & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Mental representation: A reader (pp. 3–8). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophical Psychology, School of HumanitiesUniversity of HertfordshireHatfieldUK
  2. 2.Centre for Philosophical Psychology, Department of PhilosophyUniversity of AntwerpAntwerpenBelgium

Personalised recommendations