Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 13, Issue 3, pp 395–418 | Cite as

Actual and non-actual motion: why experientialist semantics needs phenomenology (and vice versa)

Article

Abstract

Experientialist semantics has contributed to a broader notion of linguistic meaning by emphasizing notions such as construal, perspective, metaphor, and embodiment, but has suffered from an individualist concept of meaning and has conflated experiential motivations with conventional semantics. We argue that these problems can be redressed by methods and concepts from phenomenology, on the basis of a case study of sentences of non-actual motion such as “The mountain range goes all the way from Mexico to Canada.” Through a phenomenological reanalysis of proposals of Talmy, Langacker, and Matlock, we show that non-actual motion is both experientially and linguistically non-unitary. At least three different features of human consciousness—enactive perception, visual scanning, and imagination—constitute experiential motivations for non-actual motion sentences, and each of these could be related to phenomenological analyses of human intentionality. The second problem is addressed by proposing that the experiential motivations of non-actual motion sentences can be viewed as sedimented through “passive” processes of acquisition and social transmission and that this implies an interactive loop between experience and language, yielding losses in terms of original experience, but gains in terms of communal signification. Something that is underestimated by phenomenology is that what is sedimented are not only intentional objects such as states of affairs, but aspects of how they are given, i.e., the original, temporal, bodily experiences themselves. Since cognitive semantics has emphasized such aspects of meaning, we suggest that phenomenology can itself benefit from experientialist semantics, especially when it turns its focus from prepredicative to predicative, linguistic intentionality.

Keywords

Cognitive semantics Fictive motion Grounding Language–consciousness interactionism Mental simulation Phenomenology Sedimentation Subjective motion 

References

  1. Barsalou, L. W. (1999a). Perceptual symbol systems. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 577–660.Google Scholar
  2. Barsalou, L. W. (1999b). Language comprehension: Archival memory or preparation for situated action? Discourse Processes, 28, 61–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 71, 230–244.Google Scholar
  4. Barsalou, L. W. (2009). Simulation, situated conceptualization, and prediction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London: Biological Sciences, 364, 1281–1289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bergen, B., Lindsay, S., Matlock, T., & Narayanan, S. (2007). Spatial and linguistic aspects of visual imagery in sentence comprehension. Cognitive Science 31, 733–764.Google Scholar
  6. Blomberg, J. & Zlatev, J. (2011). “Fictive motion”: Experiential motivations and typological constraints. Oral presentation at the conference SALC III, Copenhagen, June 16, 2011.Google Scholar
  7. Blomberg, J. & Zlatev, J. (2012). Different experiential motivations for non-actual motion. Oral presentation at the conference Language, Culture, Mind V, Lisbon, June 28, 2012.Google Scholar
  8. Bohnemeyer, J. (2010). The language-specificity of conceptual structure: Path, fictive motion, and time relations. In B. Malt & P. Wolff (Eds.), Words and the mind: How words capture human experience (pp. 111–137). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Brandt, L. (2009). Subjectivity in the act of representing: The case for subjective motion and change. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 573–601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bundgaard, P. A. (2010). Husserl and language. In D. Schmicking & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 368–399). Dortrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Croft, W. (2003). Typology and universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Gallagher, S. (2008). Neural simulation and social cognition. In J. A. Pineda (Ed.), Mirror neuron systems: The role of mirroring processes in social cognition (pp. 355–371). Totowa: Humana Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Gallagher, S. (2012). Neurons, neonates and narrative: From empathetic resonance to empathetic understanding. In A. Foolen, U. Lüdtke, T. Racine, & J. Zlatev (Eds.), Moving ourselves—Moving others: Motion and emotion in intersubjectivity, consciousness, and language (pp. 167–198). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  14. Gallagher, S. & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  15. Hume, D. (1748). An enquiry concerning human understanding. http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/9662. Accessed 13 Jan 2013.
  16. Husserl, E. (1970a). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press (original work published 1954).Google Scholar
  17. Husserl, E. (1970b). The origin of geometry (D. Carr, Trans.). In E. Husserl (Ed.), The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (pp. 353–378). Evanston: Northwestern University Press. original work published 1939.Google Scholar
  18. Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and Judgement. Trans. J. S. Churchill, & K. Ameriks. Evanston: Routledge.Google Scholar
  19. Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy (Trans. F. Kersten). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  20. Itkonen, E. (2008). Concerning the role of consciousness in linguistics. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(6), 15–33.Google Scholar
  21. Johnson, M. (1987). The body in the mind. The bodily basis of meaning, imagination and reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  22. Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  24. Langacker, R. (1987). Foundations of cognitive grammar: Theoretical prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Langacker, R. (1990). Concept, image, and symbol: The cognitive basis of grammar. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  26. Langacker, R. (2001). Dynamicity in grammar. Axiomathes, 12, 7–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Langacker, R. (2006). Subjectification, grammaticization, and conceptual archetypes. In A. Athanasiadou, C. Canakis, & B. Cornillie (Eds.), Subjectification: Various paths to subjectivity (pp. 17–40). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  28. Matlock, T. (2004a). The conceptual motivation of fictive motion. In G. Radden & K.-U. Panther (Eds.), Studies in linguistic motivation (pp. 221–248). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  29. Matlock, T. (2004b). Fictive motion as cognitive simulation. Memory and Cognition, 32(8), 1389–1400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Matlock, T. (2010). Abstract motion is no longer abstract. Language and Cognition, 2(2), 243–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Matsumoto, Y. (1996). Subjective motion and English and Japanese verbs. Cognitive Linguistics, 7(2), 183–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Moran, D. (2005). Edmund Husserl: Founder of phenomenology. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
  33. Overgaard, S. (2012). Visual perception and self-movement: Another look. In A. Foolen, U. Lüdtke, T. Racine, & J. Zlatev (Eds.), Moving ourselves—Moving others: Motion and emotion in intersubjectivity, consciousness, and language (pp. 81–104). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Pecher, D., & Zwaan, R. A. (2005). The role of perception and action in memory, language, and thinking. In D. Pecher & R. A. Zwaan (Eds.), Grounding cognition. The role of perception and action in memory, language, and thinking (pp. 1–8). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Richardson, D., & Matlock, T. (2007). The integration of figurative language and static depictions: An eye movement study of fictive motion. Cognition, 102(1), 129–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Sokolowski, R. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Sonesson, G. (1989). Pictorial concepts. Inquiries into the semiotic heritage and its relevance for the analysis of the visual world. Lund: Aris/Lund University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Sonesson, G. (2009). The view from Husserl’s lectern: considerations on the role of phenomenology in cognitive semiotics. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 16(3–4), 107–148.Google Scholar
  39. Steinbock, A. J. (1995). Home and Beyond – Generative Phenomenology after Husserl. Evanston: Northwestern University PressGoogle Scholar
  40. Sweetser, E. (1990). From etymology to pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Talmy, L. (1983). How language structures space. Cognitive Science Program, Institute of Cognitive Studies, University of California at Berkeley.Google Scholar
  42. Talmy, L. (2000). Toward a cognitive semantics (Vol. 1). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  43. Thompson, E. (2007a). Look again: phenomenology and mental imagery. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 137–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Thompson, E. (2007b). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology and the sciences of mind. London: Belkarp.Google Scholar
  45. Woelert, P. (2011). Human cognition, space, and the sedimentation of meaning. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(1), 113–137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl's phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Zlatev, J. (1997). Situated embodiment: Studies in the emergence of spatial meaning. Stockholm: Gotab.Google Scholar
  48. Zlatev, J. (2007). Spatial semantics. In D. Geeraerts & H. Cuyckens (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of cognitive linguistics (pp. 318–350). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Zlatev, J. (2010). Phenomenology and cognitive linguistics. In D. Schmicking & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 415–443). Dortrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Zlatev, J., Blomberg, J., & David, C. (2010). Translocation, language and the categorization of experience. In V. Evans & P. Chilton (Eds.), Space in language and cognition: The state of the art and new directions (pp. 389–418). London: Equinox.Google Scholar
  51. Zlatev, J., Blomberg, J., & Magnusson, U. (2012). Metaphors and subjective experience: motion-emotion metaphors in English, Swedish, Bulgarian and Thai. In A. Foolen, U. Lüdtke, T. Racine, & J. Zlatev (Eds.), Moving ourselves—Moving others: Motion and emotion in intersubjectivity, consciousness, and language (pp. 423–450). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Zwaan, R., Madden, C., Yaxley, R., & Aveyard, M. (2004). Moving words: Dynamic representations in language comprehension. Cognitive Science, 28(4), 611–619.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Centre for Languages and Literature (CLL)Lund UniversityLundSweden

Personalised recommendations