Advertisement

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 7, Issue 4, pp 563–583 | Cite as

The place of description in phenomenology’s naturalization

  • Mark W. BrownEmail author
Article

Abstract

The recent move to naturalize phenomenology through a mathematical protocol is a significant advance in consciousness research. It enables a new and fruitful level of dialogue between the cognitive sciences and phenomenology of such a nuanced kind that it also prompts advancement in our phenomenological analyses. But precisely what is going on at this point of ‘dialogue’ between phenomenological descriptions and mathematical algorithms, the latter of which are based on dynamical systems theory? It will be shown that what is happening is something more than a mere ‘passing of the baton’ from phenomenology to mathematics. For this sophisticated naturalization to prove a worthy endeavour it must produce more than just correlation, it must prove some form of interrelation to the extent that phenomenology is deterministic. But such interrelational and deterministic requirements are the start of a slippery slope, and it will be argued that this slope only loses more friction once a further demand of formal and precise descriptions is made of phenomenology. Such deterministic and formally precise demands misconstrue phenomenology’s ideal goal of a unification of genuine/originary reason and truth. Not a deductive and definitive discipline, phenomenology is rather from the outset descriptive and critical. Phenomenology’s descriptive beginnings will thus be employed as an essential barrier to the naturalization of phenomenology.

Keywords

Phenomenology Neuro-phenomenology Naturalization Description Dynamical systems theory 

Notes

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2006 meetings of the Husserl Circle in Boston, and the International Association for Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences in Durham. I would like to thank both forums for their many helpful comments and criticisms. I am also indebted to two anonymous referees and editor Dan Zahavi for their numerous insights and criticisms.

References

  1. Bachelard, S. (1968). A study of Husserl’s formal and transcendental logic. Evanston: Northwestern University Press Translated by Lester E. Embree.Google Scholar
  2. Blosser, P. (1990). The a priori in phenomenology and the legacy of logical empiricism. Philosophy Today, 34, 195–205.Google Scholar
  3. Clark, A. (1997). Being there:Pputting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Da Silva, J. J. (2000). Husserl’s two notions of completeness: Husserl and Hilbert on completeness and imaginary elements in mathematics. Synthese, 125, 417–438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. De Boer, T. (1976). The descriptive method of Franz Brentano: Its two functions and their significance for phenomenology. In L. McAlister (Ed.) The Philosophy of Brentano pp. 101–107. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  6. De Caro, M., & Macarthur, D. (2004). Introduction: The nature of naturalism. In M. De Caro, & D. Macarthur (Eds.) Naturalism in question pp. 1–17. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  7. De Preester, H. (2006). Naturalism and transcendentalism in the naturalization of phenomenology. New Ideas in Psychology, 24, 41–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown.Google Scholar
  9. Depraz, N. (1999). When transcendental genesis encounters the naturalization project. In Jean Petitot (Ed.) Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 464–489). California: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Drummond, J.J. (1992). Indirect mathematization in the physical sciences. In L. Hardy, & L. Embree (Eds.) Phenomenology of the natural sciences (pp. 71–92). Netherlands: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  11. Fisette, D. (2004). Erläuterungen: Logical analysis vs. phenomenological descriptions. In R. Feist (Ed.) Husserl and the sciences: Selected perspectives (pp. 69–98). Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press.Google Scholar
  12. Gallagher, S., & Varela, F. J. (2003). Redrawing the map and resetting the time: Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 29(Supplementary Volume), 93–132.Google Scholar
  13. Haaparanta, L. (1995). On the possibility of pure epistemology: A Husserlian point of view. In mind and cognition: philosophical perspectives on cognitive science and artificial intelligence. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 58, 151–167.Google Scholar
  14. Haaparanta, L. (1999). On the possibility of naturalistic and of pure epistemology. Synthese, 118, 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hill, C. O. (1991). Word and object in Husserl, Frege, and Russell: The roots of twentieth-century philosophy. Athens: Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hill, C. O. (2000). Husserl’s Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. In C. O. Hill, & G. E. R. Haddock (Eds.) Husserl or Frege? Meaning, objectivity, and mathematics (pp. 161–178). Illinois: Open Court.Google Scholar
  17. Hill, C. O. (2002). Tackling three of Frege’s problems: Edmund Husserl on sets and manifolds. Axiomathes, 13, 79–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hopkins, B. C. (1991). Phenomenological self-critique of its descriptive method. Husserl Studies, 8, 129–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (1996). Connectionism and the philosophy of psychology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Husserl, E. (1965). Philosophy as rigorous science. In Phenomenology and the crisis of philosophy (pp. 71–147). New York: Harper & Row. Translated by Quentin Lauer.Google Scholar
  21. Husserl, E. (1969). Formal and transcendental logic. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Translated by Dorion Cairns.Google Scholar
  22. Husserl, E. (1974). Kant and the idea of transcendental philosophy. The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 5, 9–56 Translated by Ted E. Klein Jr., & William E. Pohl.Google Scholar
  23. Husserl, E. (1975). Introduction to the logical investigations. A draft of a preface to the logical investigations (1913). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Translated by Philip J. Bossert, & Curtis H. Peters. Edited by Eugen Fink.Google Scholar
  24. Husserl, E. (1977a). Phenomenological psychology: Lectures, summer semester; 1925. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Translated by John Scanlon.Google Scholar
  25. Husserl, E. (1977b). The task and significance of the logical investigations. In J. N. Mohanty (Ed.) Readings on Edmund Husserl’s logical investigations (pp. 197–215). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Translated by J. N. Mohanty.Google Scholar
  26. Husserl, E. (1980). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, third book. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Translated by Ted E. Klein, & William E. Pohl.Google Scholar
  27. Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, first book. Dordrecht: Kluwer Translated by F. Kersten.Google Scholar
  28. Husserl, E. (1997). Phenomenology. Encyclopaedia Britannica article. Draft D. In T. Sheehan, & R. E. Palmer (Eds.) Psychological and transcendental phenomenology and the confrontation with Heidegger (1927–1931) (pp. 159–179 ). Translated by T. Sheehan, & R. E. Palmer.Google Scholar
  29. Husserl, E. (1999a). Cartesian meditations. Dordrecht: Kluwer Translated by Dorion Cairns.Google Scholar
  30. Husserl, E. (1999b). The Idea of Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Kluwer Translated by Lee Hardy.Google Scholar
  31. Husserl, E. (2001a). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis. Lectures on transcendental logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Translated by Anthony J. Steinbock.Google Scholar
  32. Husserl, E. (2001b). Logical investigations. London: Routledge 2 volumes. Translated by J. N. Findlay. Edited by Dermot Moran.Google Scholar
  33. Husserl, E. (2003). Philosophy of arithmetic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Translated by Dallas Willard.Google Scholar
  34. Husserl, E. (2006). The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Springer Translated by Ingo Farin, & James G. Hart.Google Scholar
  35. Kornblith, H. (1994). Naturalism: Both metaphysical and epistemological. In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling Jr., & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.) Midwest studies in philosophy XIX: Philosophical naturalism (pp. 39–52). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  36. Luft, S. (1998). Husserl’s phenomenological discovery of the natural attitude. Continental Philosophy Review, 31, 153–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Lutz, A. (2002). Toward a neurophenomenology as an account of generative passages: A first empirical case study. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 133–167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Lutz, A., & Thompson, E. (2003). Neurophenomenology: Integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 31–52.Google Scholar
  39. Majer, U. (1997). Husserl and Hilbert on completeness: A neglected chapter in early twentieth century foundations of mathematics. Synthese, 110, 37–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
  41. Miller, J. P. (1982). Numbers in presence and absence: A study of Husserl’s philosophy of mathematics. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  42. Mohanty, J. N. (1974). ‘Life-world’ and ‘a priori’ in Husserl’s later thought. Analecta Husserliana, 3, 46–65.Google Scholar
  43. Moran, D. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  44. Moran, D. (2004). Husserl’s phenomenology of perception. Proceedings of the Husserl Circle. At Georgetown University. 34th Annual Meeting. Washington: Academx, pp. 113–136.Google Scholar
  45. Moran, D. (2006). Husserl’s transcendental critique of naturalism. Paper presented at the Essex Phenomenology Workshop, Transcendental Philosophy and Naturalism Project. UCL, London 16 June 2006.Google Scholar
  46. Münch, D. (2002). The relation of Husserl’s logical investigations to descriptive psychology and cognitive science. . In D. Zahavi, & F. Stjernfelt (Eds.) One hundred years of phenomenology: Husserl logical investigations revisited (pp. 199–215). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  47. Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 82, 435–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Rinofner-Kreidl, S. (2003). What is wrong with naturalizing epistemology? A phenomenologist’s reply. In R. Feist (Ed.) Husserl and the sciences: Selected perspectives (pp. 41–68). Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press.Google Scholar
  49. Roy, J.-M. (1999). Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In J. Petitot, et al. (Ed.) Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 1–80). California: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Rudrauf, D. (2003). From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology: Fransisco Varela’s exploration of the biophysics of being. Biological Research, 36, 27–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Thomasson, A. L. (2003). Introspection and phenomenological method. Phenomenology and the cognitive Sciences, 2, 239–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Tieszen, R. (2005). Phenomenology, logic, and the philosophy of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Tito, J. M. (1990). Logic in the Husserlian context. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  54. van Gelder, T., & Port, R. F. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. F. Port, & T. van Gelder (Eds.) Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 1–43). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  55. Varela, F. J. (1997). The naturalization of phenomenology as the transcendence of nature: Searching for generative mutual constraints. Alter: Revue de Phénoménologie, 5, 355–381.Google Scholar
  56. Villela-Petit, M. (1999). Cognitive psychology and the transcendental theory of knowledge. In J. Petitot (Ed.) Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 508–524). California: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Zahavi, D. (2004). Phenomenology and the project of naturalization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, 331–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Murdoch UniversityPerthAustralia

Personalised recommendations