Skip to main content
Log in

Restating the role of phenomenal experience in the formation and maintenance of the Capgras delusion

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent times, explanations of the Capgras delusion have tended to emphasise the cognitive dysfunction that is believed to occur at the second stage of two-stage models. This is generally viewed as a response to the inadequacies of the one-stage account. Whilst accepting that some form of cognitive disruption is a necessary part of the aetiology of the Capgras delusion, I nevertheless argue that the emphasis placed on this second-stage is to the detriment of the important role played by the phenomenology underlying the disorder, both in terms of the formation and maintenance of the delusional belief. This paper therefore proposes an interactionist two-stage model in which the phenomenal experience of the Capgras patient is examined, emphasised, and its relation to top-down processing discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are reports of Capgras patients who claim to perceive differences in the impostor. However, when pressed on what exactly these differences are, they have difficulty pointing them out (see Young, 1999).

  2. In rejecting Ratcliffe’s examples, I am not ruling out altogether the possibility that there may be other everyday examples that are equivalent to the phenomenal experience of the Capgras patient. I thank the anonymous referee for drawing my attention to this point.

  3. For a detailed discussion on this difference, see Dretske (1995, 2000).

  4. I am grateful to Matthew Ratcliffe for this example.

  5. In Young (in press) I try to clarify further what I mean by recognising and yet not recognising someone, as well as the role familiarity plays in this distinction. In the discussion, I contrast recognition-familiarity with estrangement.

  6. See Breen, Caine and Coltheart (2000) for a more detailed discussion on this, and also Haxby, Hoffman and Gobbini (2000) and Haxby et al. (2001).

  7. When prosopagnosic patients are presented with a familiar rather than an unfamiliar face, despite their lack of conscious recognition, there is an increase in SCR. This difference is often interpreted as a measure of unconscious recognition and has been associated with one’s sense of familiarity (see Bauer, 1984, and Tranel & Damasio, 1985).

  8. Actually, Young (1999) noted that, when questioned more closely, Capgras patients report a general sense of oddness and unfamiliarity, and of things ‘not quite being right.’ This is what one might expect if the patient is less able to establish affective links with those around him, or even elicit emotional significance from certain places or objects. However, this general, and much milder, sense of ‘oddness’ does not lead to delusional belief.

  9. Although it could be argued that differences in the underlying neuropathology produce different experiences. Something in this difference leads one group to form delusional beliefs and another group not to.

  10. I appreciate that this statement is difficult to prove (to say the least), and problematic because of it. However, I hope that the argument presented throughout this paper provides some support at least for the possibility of the claim being true.

  11. See Davies and Coltheart (2000) for a more detailed example of this. Their EHBC account proposes a progression from experience to hypothesis to belief to circumscription.

  12. I am not trying to endorse the view that Capgras patients would be much more susceptible to all forms of visual illusion. Instead, I am simply trying to draw a parallel between our normal and active perceptual processing and that of the Capgras patient.

  13. Huq, Garety and Hemsley (1988) and Garety, Hemsley and Wessely (1991) noted that people with delusions tend to request less information before drawing a conclusion about the likely outcome of an event, preferring instead to jump to conclusions.

References

  • Bauer, R. M. (1984). Autonomic recognition of names and faces in prosopagnosia: A neuropsychological application of the guilty knowledge test. Neuropsychologia, 22, 457–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., & Pacherie, E. (2005). In defence of the doxastic conception of delusions. Mind and Language, 20(2), 163–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2001). Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorder. Mind and Language, 16(5), 457–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berson, R. J. (1983). Capgras’ syndrome. American Journal of Psychiatry, 140(8), 969–978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2005). Delusions and the background of rationality. Mind and Language, 20(2), 189–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breen, N., Caine, D., & Coltheart, M. (2000). Models of face recognition and delusional misidentification: A critical review. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 17(1/2/3), 55–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capgras, J., & Reboul-Lachaux, J. (1923). L’illusion des ‘soises’ dans un délire systématisé chronique. Bulletin de la Société Clinique de Médicine Mentale, 11, 6–16. In M. D. Enoch & W. H. Trethowan (Eds.), Uncommon psyciatric syndromes. Bristol: John Wright and Sons Ltd, 1979.

  • Christodoulou, G. N. (1977). The Syndrome of Capgras. British Journal of Psychiatry, 130, 556–564.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christodoulou, G. N. (1991). The delusional misidentification syndromes. British Journal of Psychiatry, 159, 65–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P., Ramachandran, V. S., & Sejnowski, T. (1994). A critique of pure vision. In C. Koch & J. L Davies (Eds.), Large-scale neuronal theories of the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., & Coltheart, M. (2000). Introduction: Pathologies of belief. Mind and Language, 15(1), 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (2000). Perception, knowledge, and belief: Selected essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, H. D., & Lewis, L. (2001). Capgras delusion: A window on face recognition. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5(4), 149–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, H. D., & Young, A. W. (1990). Accounting for delusional misidentification. British Journal of Psychiatry, 157, 239–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, H. D., Young, A. W., Quayle, A., & de Pauw, K. W. (1997). Reduced autonomic responses to faces in Capgras delusion. Proceedings of the Royal Society: Biological Sciences, B246, 1084–1092.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garety, P. A., Hemsley, D. R., & Wessely, S. (1991). Reasoning in deluded schizophrenic and paranid patients: Biases in performance on a probabilistic inference task. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 179, 194–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerrans, P. (2002). A one-stage explanation of the cotard delusion. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 9(1), 47–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haxby, J. V., Gobbini, M. I., Furey, M. L., Ishai, A., Schouten, J. L., & Pietrini, P. (2001). Distributed and overlapping representations of faces and objects in ventral temporal cortex. Science, 293(5539), 2425–2430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haxby, J. V., Hoffman, E. A., & Gobbini, M. I. (2000). The distributed human neural system for face perception. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4(6), 223–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirstein, W., & Ramachandran, V. S. (1997). Capgras’ syndrome: A novel probe for understanding the neural representation of the identity of familiarity of persons. Proceedings of the Royal Society: Biological Sciences, B246, 437–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., & Rosenberg, R. (2005). Unusual experiences, reality testing and delusions of alien control. Mind and Language, 20(2), 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huq, S. F., Garety, P. A., & Hemsley, D. R. (1988). Probabilistic judgements in deluded and non-deluded subjects. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 40A, 801–812.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klee, R. (2004). Why some delusions are necessarily inexplicable beliefs. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 11(1), 25–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langdon, R., & Coltheart, M. (2000). The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions. Mind and Language, 15(1), 184–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maher, B. A. (1974). Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder. Journal of Individual Psychology, 30, 98–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, B. A. (1988). Anomalous experience and delusional thinking: The logic of explanations. In T. F. Oltmanns & B. A. Maher (Eds.), Delusional beliefs (pp. 15–33). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, B. A. (1999). Anomalous experience in everyday life: Its significance for psychopathology. The Monist, 82(4), 547–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2004). Interpreting delusions. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, 3, 25–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1969). Being and nothingness (H. Barnes, trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, B. G. (1992). Modeling and critiquing the confirmation bias in human reasoning. Systems, Man and Cybernetics, 22(5), 972–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, T., & Young, A. W. (1997). Delusions and brain injury: The philosophy and psychology of belief. Mind and Language, 12(3/4), 327–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. R. (1985). Knowledge without awareness: An automatic index of facial recognition by prosopagnosics. Science, 228, 1453–1454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tranel, D., Damasio, H., & Damasio, A. R. (1995). Double dissociation between overt and covert face recognition. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 7(4), 425–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, A. W. (1999). Delusions. The Monist, 82(4), 571–589.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, A. W. (2000). Wondrous strange: The neuropsychology of abnormal beliefs. Mind and Language, 15(1), 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, G. (in press). Clarifying ‘familiarity’: Examining differences in the phenomenal experiences of patients suffering from prosopagnosia and Capgras delusion. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology.

  • Young, A. W., & de Pauw, K. W. (2002). One stage is not enough. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 9(1), 5–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Garry Young.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Young, G. Restating the role of phenomenal experience in the formation and maintenance of the Capgras delusion. Phenom Cogn Sci 7, 177–189 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9048-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9048-0

Key words

Navigation