Advertisement

Factive islands and meaning-driven unacceptability

  • Bernhard Schwarz
  • Alexandra Simonenko
Article
  • 11 Downloads

Abstract

It is often proposed that the unacceptability of a semantically interpretable sentence can be rooted in its meaning. Elaborating on Oshima (in Washio T, et al (eds) New frontiers in artificial intelligence, Springer, Berlin, 2007), we argue that the meaning-driven unacceptability of factive islands must make reference to felicity conditions, and cannot be reduced to the triviality of propositional content. We also observe, again elaborating on Oshima, that the triviality of factive islands need not be logical, but can be relative to a listener’s background assumptions. These findings call for a revision of a prevalent view about meaning-driven unacceptability, according to which unacceptability results from triviality that is both propositional and logical.

Keywords

Factive islands Questions Unacceptability Triviality Felicity conditions Presuppositions Uniqueness 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Abrusán, Márta. 2007. Contradiction and grammar: The case of weak islands. PhD dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  2. Abrusán, Márta. 2011. Presuppositional and negative islands: A semantic account. Natural Language Semantics 19: 257–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Abrusán, Márta. 2014. Weak island semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Abusch, Dorit. 2010. Presupposition triggering from alternatives. Journal of Semantics 27: 37–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Barwise, Jon, and Robin Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 4: 159–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Beck, Sigrid, and Hotze Rullmann. 1999. A flexible approach to exhaustivity in questions. Natural Language Semantics 7: 249–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Buccola, Brian, and Benjamin Spector. 2016. Maximality and modified numerals. Linguistics and Philosophy 39: 151–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chemla, Emmanuel. 2009. Presuppositions of quantified sentences: Experimental data. Natural Language Semantics 17: 299–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2013. Logic in grammar: Polarity, free choice, and intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cooper, Robin. 1983. Quantification and semantic theory. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Cremers, Alexandre. 2016. On the semantics of embedded questions. PhD dissertation, Ecole Normale Superieure, Paris.Google Scholar
  12. Cremers, Alexandre, and Emmanuel Chemla. 2016. A psycholinguistic study of the exhaustive readings of embedded questions. Journal of Semantics 33: 49–85.Google Scholar
  13. Cresswell, Max J. 1976. The semantics of degree. In Montague grammar, ed. Barbara H. Partee, 261–292. New York: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dayal, Veneeta. 1996. Locality in wh quantification: Questions and relative clauses in hindi. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Del Pinal, Guillermo. 2017. The logicality of language: a new take on triviality, “ungrammaticality”, and Logical Form.  https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12235.
  16. Dowty, David R. 1979. Word meaning and Montague Grammar: The semantics of verbs and times in generative semantics and in Montague’s PTQ. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fox, Danny. 2007. Too many alternatives: Density, symmetry, and other predicaments. In Proceedings of SALT 17, ed. Masayuki Gibson and Tova Friedman, 22–24. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Fox, Danny, and Martin Hackl. 2006. The universal density of measurement. Linguistics and Philosophy 29: 537–586.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Gajewski, Jon. 2002. L-analyticity and natural language. MIT: Manuscript.Google Scholar
  20. Gajewski, Jon. 2009. Innocent exclusion is not contradiction free. Manuscript: University of Connecticut.Google Scholar
  21. Gentile, Francesco, and Bernhard Schwarz. 2018. A uniqueness puzzle: How many-questions and non-distributive predication. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 21, ed. Robert Truswell, Chris Cummins, Caroline Heycock, Brian Rabern, and Hannah Rohde, 445–462. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh.Google Scholar
  22. Geurts, Bart, and Bob van Tiel. 2015. When “all the five circles are four”: New exercises in domain restriction. Topoi 35: 1–14.Google Scholar
  23. Groenendijk, Jeroen, and Martin Stokhof. 1984. Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. PhD dissertation, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  24. Guerzoni, Elena. 2003. Why even ask?: on the pragmatics of questions and the semantics of answers. PhD dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  25. Hamblin, Charles L. 1973. Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language 10: 41–53.Google Scholar
  26. Heim, Irene. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. In Proceedings of the Second West Coast Conference in Linguistics, ed. D. Flickinger, M. Barlow, and M. Wescoat, 249–260. Stanford: Stanford University.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Heim, Irene. 1991. Artikel und Definitheit. In Semantik: ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung, ed. Arnim von Stechow, and Dieter Wunderlich, 487–535. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  28. Heim, Irene. 2000. Degree operators and scope. In Proceedings of SALT 10, ed. B. Jackson and T. Matthews, 40–64. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Heim, Irene. 2006. Little. In Proceedings of SALT 16, ed. Masayuki Gibson and Jonathan Howell, 35–58. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  30. Heim, Irene, and Angelika Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in generative grammar. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  31. Higginbotham, James. 1993. Interrogatives. In The view from building 20, ed. Kenneth Hale, and Jay Keyser, 195–227. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  32. Kaplan, David. 1989. Demonstratives. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. Joseph Almog, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein, 481–563. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Karttunen, Lauri. 1977. Syntax and semantics of questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 1: 3–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Keenan, Edward L. 1987. A semantic definition of ‘indefinite NP’. In The representation of (in)definiteness, ed. Eric J. Reuland and Alice G.B. ter Meulen, 286–317. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  35. Kennedy, Christopher. 2015. A “de-Fregean” semantics (and neo-Gricean pragmatics) for modified and unmodified numerals. Semantics and Pragmatics 8: 1–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. King, David. 2001. Complex demonstratives: A quantificational account. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  37. Klinedinst, Nathan, and Daniel Rothschild. 2011. Exhaustivity in questions with non-factives. Semantics and Pragmatics 4: 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Krifka, Manfred. 1995. The semantics and pragmatics of polarity items. Linguistic Analysis 25: 209–257.Google Scholar
  39. Lahiri, Utpal. 1998. Focus and negative polarity in Hindi. Natural Language Semantics 6: 57–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Oshima, David Y. 2007. On factive islands: pragmatic anomaly vs. pragmatic infelicity. In New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence: Proceedings of JSAI 2006 (LNCS 4384), ed. T. Washio, K. Satoh, H. Takeda, and A. Inokuchi, 147–161. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  41. Robert, Stalnaker. 1978. Assertion. In Syntax and semantics, vol. 9, ed. Peter Cole, 315–332. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  42. Rooryck, Johan. 1992. Negative and factive islands revisited. Journal of Linguistics 28: 343–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Ross, John R. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. PhD dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  44. Sæbø Kjell Johan. 2016. “How” questions and the manner-method distinction. Synthese 193: 3169–3194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Schlenker, Philippe. 2008. Presupposition projection: Explanatory strategies. Theoretical Linguistics 34: 287–316.Google Scholar
  46. Schlenker, Philippe. 2009. Local contexts. Semantics & Pragmatics 2: 1–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Schwarz, Bernhard, and Alexandra Simonenko. 2018a. Decomposing universal projection in questions. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 22, ZASPiL 61(2), ed. Uli Sauerland and Stephanie Solt, 361–374. Berlin: Leibniz-Centre General Linguistics.Google Scholar
  48. Schwarz, Bernhard, and Alexandra Simonenko. 2018b. Wh-restrictor plurality and question pragmatics. Talk at Generative Linguistics in the Old World (GLOW) 41 Workshop on the Grammar and Pragmatics of Interrogatives and their (Special) Uses, Research Institute for Linguistics of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences, Budapest, April 14, 2018.Google Scholar
  49. Schwarz, Bernhard, and Alexandra Simonenko. In press. On the logical makeup of how- and why-questions. In Proceedings of SALT 28, ed. Sireemas Maspong and Brynhildur Stefánsdóttir. Washington, DC: LSA.Google Scholar
  50. Schwarz, Bernhard. In press. On the locus of question exhaustification. In Proceedings of NELS 48, ed. Sherry Hucklebridge and Max Nelson. Amherst, MA: GLSA.Google Scholar
  51. Simonenko, Alexandra. 2014. Structural triggers of the loss of scopelessness. In Proceedings of WCCFL 32, ed. Ulrike Steindl, Thomas Borer, Huilin Fang, Alfredo García Pardo, Peter Guekguezian, Brian Hsu, Charlie O’Hara, and Iris Chuoying Ouyang, 191–206. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Google Scholar
  52. Simonenko, Alexandra. 2016. Semantics of DP islands: The case of questions. Journal of Semantics 33: 661–702.Google Scholar
  53. Spector, Benjamin. 2018. Revisiting weak exhaustivity. Slides for presentation at workshop ‘Meaning in non-canonical questions’. Konstanz: University of Konstanz.Google Scholar
  54. Spector, Benjamin, and Paul Egré. 2015. A uniform semantics for embedded interrogatives: An answer, not necessarily the answer. Synthese 192: 1729–1784.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Szabolcsi, Anna, and Frans Zwarts. 1993. Weak islands and an algebraic semantics for scope taking. Natural Language Semantics 1: 235–284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Theiler, Nadine, Floris Roelofsen, and Maria Aloni. 2016. Truthful resolutions: A new perspective on false-answer sensitivity. In Proceedings of SALT 26, ed. Mary Moroney, Carol-Rose Little, Jacob Collard, and Dan Burgdorf, 122–141. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Uegaki, Wataru. 2015. Interpreting questions under attitudes. PhD dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  58. Unger, Peter. 1977. The uniqueness in causation. American Philosophical Quarterly 14: 177–188.Google Scholar
  59. von Fintel, Kai. 1993. Exceptive constructions. Natural Language Semantics 1: 123–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. von Fintel, Kai. 2008. What is presupposition accommodation, again? Philosophical Perspectives 22: 137–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Xiang, Yimei. 2016. Interpreting questions with non-exhaustive answers. PhD dissertation, Harvard University.Google Scholar
  62. Zucchi, Alessandro. 1995. The ingredients of definiteness and the definiteness effect. Natural Language Semantics 3: 33–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of LinguisticsMcGill UniversityMontrealCanada
  2. 2.Faculty of Arts and Philosophy, Department of LinguisticsResearch Foundation Flanders (FWO)/Ghent UniversityGhentBelgium

Personalised recommendations