Natural Language Semantics

, Volume 20, Issue 4, pp 391–429 | Cite as

Maximize Presupposition and Gricean reasoning

Article

Abstract

Recent semantic research has made increasing use of a principle, Maximize Presupposition, which requires that under certain circumstances the strongest possible presupposition be marked. This principle is generally taken to be irreducible to standard Gricean reasoning because the forms that are in competition have the same assertive content. We suggest, however, that Maximize Presupposition might be reducible to the theory of scalar implicatures. (i)First, we consider a special case: the speaker utters a sentence with a presupposition p which is not initially taken for granted by the addressee, but the latter takes the speaker to be an authority on the matter. Signaling the presupposition provides new information to the addressee; but it also follows from the logic of presupposition qua common belief that the presupposition is thereby satisfied (Stalnaker, Ling Philos 25(5–6):701–721, 2002). (ii) Second, we generalize this solution to other cases. We assume that even when p is common belief, there is a very small chance that the addressee might forget it (‘Fallibility’); in such cases, marking a presupposition will turn out to generate new information by re-establishing part of the original context. We also adopt from Raj Singh (Nat Lang Semantics 19(2):149–168, 2011) the hypothesis that presupposition maximization is computed relative to local contexts—and we assume that these too are subject to Fallibility; this accounts for cases in which the information that justifies the presupposition is linguistically provided. (iii) Finally, we suggest that our assumptions have benefits in the domain of implicatures: they make it possible to reinterpret Magri’s ‘blind’ (i.e. context-insensitive) implicatures as context-sensitive implicatures which just happen to be misleading.

Keywords

Presupposition Implicatures Pragmatics Antipresuppositions Implicated presuppositions 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Beaver, David, and Emiel Krahmer. 2001. A partial account of presupposition projection. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10: 147–182. doi:10.1023/A:1008371413822.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Chemla, Emmanuel. 2007a. Présuppositions et implicatures scalaires: études formelles et expérimentales. Doctoral dissertation, école des Hautes études en Sciences Sociales, Paris.Google Scholar
  3. Chemla, Emmanuel. 2007b. French both: A gap in the theory of antipresupposition. Snippets 15: 4–5.Google Scholar
  4. Chemla, Emmanuel. 2008a. Similarity: Towards a unified account of scalar implicatures, free choice permission and presupposition projection. Manuscript, LSCP, Paris.Google Scholar
  5. Chemla, Emmanuel. 2008b. An epistemic step for anti-presuppositions. Journal of Semantics 25: 141–173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chemla, Emmanuel, and Benjamin Spector. 2011. Experimental evidence for embedded scalar implicatures. Journal of Semantics 28 (3): 359–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. To appear. The grammatical view of scalarity and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In Semantics: An international handbook of Natural Language meaning, ed. Paul Portner, Claudia Maienborn, and Klaus von Heusinger. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  8. Cooper, R. 1983. Quantification and syntactic theory. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  9. Fagin, R., J. Halpern, Y. Moses, and M. Vardi. 1995. Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Fintel, Kai von 2008. What is presupposition accommodation, again? Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1): 137–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fox, Danny. 2008. Two short notes on Schlenker’s theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical Linguistics 34 (3): 237–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. George, Benjamin. 2008a, Predicting presupposition projection: Some alternatives in the strong Kleene tradition. Manuscript, UCLA. Semantics Archive. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/DY0YTgxN/.
  13. George, Benjamin: 2008b, Presupposition repairs: A static, trivalent approach to predicting presupposition. MA thesis, UCLA. Semantics Archive. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/2ZiYmEyN/.
  14. Gettier, E. 1963. Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis 23: 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Geurts, Bart. 1999. Presupposition and pronouns. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  16. Heim, I. 1991. Artikel und Definitheit. In Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung, ed. A. von Stechow and D. Wunderlich, 487–534. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  17. Heim, Irene. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. In Proceedings of WCCFL 2, ed. D. Flickinger et al., 114–125. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  18. Heim, I. 2005. Features on bound pronouns. Manuscript, MIT.Google Scholar
  19. Heim, I., and A. Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in generative grammar. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  20. Kratzer, A. 2002. Facts: Particulars or information units? Linguistics and Philosophy 25(5–6): 655–670. doi:10.1023/A:1020807615085.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Magri, Giorgio. 2009. A theory of individual-level predicates based on blind mandatory scalar implicatures. Natural Language Semantics 17: 245–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Magri, Giorgio. 2011. Another argument for embedded scalar implicatures based on oddness in downward entailing contexts. In Proceedings of SALT 20, ed. Nan Li and David Lutz, 564–581. eLanguage.Google Scholar
  23. Magri, Giorgio. 2012. Is fallibility different from blindness? A reply to Schlenker (2012). Manuscript, Institut Jean-Nicod, CNRS.Google Scholar
  24. Osborne, M., and A. Rubinstein. 1994. A course in game theory. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Percus, Orin. 2006. Anti-presuppositions. In Theoretical and empirical studies of reference and anaphora: Toward the establishment of generative grammar as an empirical science. Report of the Grant-in-Aid for Scientific Research (B), Project No. 15320052, ed. A.␣Ueyama, 52–73. Washington: Japan Society for the Promotion of Science.Google Scholar
  26. Peters, Stanley. 1979. A truth-conditional formulation of Karttunen’s account of presupposition. Synthese 40: 301–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Rooth, Mats. 1996. Focus. In The handbook of contemporary semantic theory, ed. S.␣Lappin, 271–298. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  28. Sauerland, Uli. 2003. Implicated presuppositions. Handout for a talk presented at the University of Milan Bicocca.Google Scholar
  29. Sauerland, Uli. 2008. Implicated presuppositions. In Sentence and context: Language, context, and cognition, ed. A.␣Steube. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  30. Schlenker, Philippe. 2003. A plea for monsters. Linguistics and Philosophy 26: 29–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Schlenker, Philippe. 2004. Person and binding: a partial survey. Italian Journal of Linguistics/Rivista di Linguistica 16 (1): 155–218.Google Scholar
  32. Schlenker, Philippe. 2005a. The lazy Frenchman’s approach to the subjunctive. In Romance languages and linguistic theory 2003, ed. T.␣Geerts, I. van Ginneken, and H. Jacobs, 269–309. Amsterdam: Benjamins.Google Scholar
  33. Schlenker, Philippe. 2005b. Minimize restrictors! (Notes on definite descriptions, condition C and epithets) In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 2004, ed. Emar Maier, Corien Bary, and Janneke Huitink, 385–416. Nijmegen: NCS.Google Scholar
  34. Schlenker, Philippe. 2007. Transparency: An incremental theory of presupposition projection. In Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics, ed. U.␣Sauerland, and P. Stateva, 214–242. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  35. Schlenker, Philippe. 2008. Be articulate: A pragmatic theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical Linguistics 34(3): 157–212.Google Scholar
  36. Schlenker, Philippe. 2009. Local contexts. Semantics & Pragmatics 2(3): 1–78. doi:10.3765/sp.2.3.Google Scholar
  37. Schlenker, Philippe. 2010. Presuppositions and local contexts. Mind 119 (474): 377–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Schwarzschild, Roger. 1997. Interpreting accent. Manuscript, Rutgers University.Google Scholar
  39. Schwarzschild, R. 1999. GIVENness, AvoidF and other constraints on the placement of accent. Natural Language Semantics 7: 141–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Schwarzschild, R. 2004. Focus interpretations: comments on Geurts and van der Sandt (2004). Theoretical Linguistics 30 (1): 137–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Singh, Raj. 2011. Maximize Presupposition! and local contexts. Natural Language Semantics 19 (2): 149–168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Stalnaker, R. 1978. Assertion. Syntax and Semantics 9: 315–332.Google Scholar
  43. Stalnaker, R. 1998. On the representation of context. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 7 (1): 3–19. doi:10.1023/A:1008254815298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Stalnaker, R. 2002. Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5–6): 701–721.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Stanley, J. 2004. On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies 119 (1–2): 119–146. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000029353.14987.34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. van der Sandt, Rob. 1992. Presupposition projection as anaphora resolution. Journal of Semantics 9 (4): 333–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institut Jean-Nicod, CNRSParisFrance
  2. 2.New York UniversityNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations