Natural Language Semantics

, Volume 15, Issue 1, pp 1–34 | Cite as

On the meaning of some focus-sensitive particles

Article

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that the aspectual, marginality, and concessive uses of the grading particles still and already can be reduced to the fol lowing three classes of focus sensitive-grading particles: additive particles like too, scalar particles like even, and exclusive particles like only. The meaning differences among the occurrences of still (and already) are mostly reduced to the differences among these three classes of grading particles. In turn, these differences are shown to correlate with what type of object is denoted by the phrase in the scope of the particle. The proposal has repercussions also for the focus-sensitive particle again. I investigate the latter too, and I propose a parallel between the temporal and nominal domains where the contrast between still and again is analyzed along the lines of the contrast between definite and indefinite noun phrases.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Barker C. (2002). The dynamics of vagueness. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25: 1–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Barker, C. (2004). Parasitic scope. In Proceedings of SALT 14. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  3. Bennett J. (1982). Even if. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5: 403–418CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carlson G. (1987). Same and different: Consequences for syntax and semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 10: 531–565CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cinque G. (1999). Adverbs and functional heads. Oxford, Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  6. Dowty, D. (1985). A unified indexical analysis of same and different. Ms., The Ohio State University, http://www.ling.ohio-state.edu/ dowty/same-diff/same-df1.ps.Google Scholar
  7. Fintel, K. von (2000). Counterfactuals in a dynamic context. In M. Kenstowicz (Ed.), Ken Hale: A life in language (pp. 123–152). Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  8. Geurts, B., & van der Sandt, R. (2004). Interpreting focus. To appear in Theoretical Linguistics.Google Scholar
  9. Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.Google Scholar
  10. Heim I. (1990). Presupposition projection. In: van der Sandt R. (eds) Presupposition, lexical meaning and discourse processes: Workshop Reader. Nijmegen, University of NijmegenGoogle Scholar
  11. Heim I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9: 183–221CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Heim, I. (2000). Degree operators and scope. In Proceedings of SALT 10 (pp. 40–64). Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  13. Horn, L. (1969). A presuppositional analysis of ‘only’ and ‘even’. In Papers from the fifth regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society (pp. 98–107). Chicago: CLS.Google Scholar
  14. Horn L. (1970). Ain’t it hard (anymore). In: Campbell M. et al. (eds) Papers from the sixth regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Chicago, CLS, pp. 318–327Google Scholar
  15. Ippolito, M. (2004). Semantic Composition and presupposition projection in subjunctive conditionals. Ms., University of Toronto.Google Scholar
  16. Ippolito, M. (2006). Remarks on only. In J. Howell & E. Georgala (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 16. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  17. Kamp H. (2001). The importance of presupposition. In: Rohrer C., Rossdeutscher A. (eds) Linguistic form and its computation. Stanford, CSLI PublicationsGoogle Scholar
  18. Karttunen L., Peters S. (1979). Conventional implicature. In: Oh C.-K., Dinneen D.A. (eds). Syntax and semantics 11: Presupposition. New York, Academic Press, pp. 1-56Google Scholar
  19. Kennedy, C. (2003). The grammar of vagueness. Ms., Northwestern University.Google Scholar
  20. Kennedy, C., & McNally, L. (2002). Scale structure and the semantic typology of gradable predicates. Ms., Northwestern University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra.Google Scholar
  21. König E. (1977). Temporal and non-temporal uses of ‘noch’ and ‘schon’ in German. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1: 173–198Google Scholar
  22. Kratzer A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In: Eikmeyer H.-J., Rieser H. (eds). Words, worlds, and contexts. Berlin, de Gruyter, pp. 38-74Google Scholar
  23. Kratzer A. (1991). Modality. In: Stechow A.V., Wunderlich D. (eds). Semantics. An international handbook of contemporary research. Berlin, De Gruyter, pp. 639-650Google Scholar
  24. Kratzer A. (1994). Severing the external argument from its verb. In: Rooryck J., Zaring L. (eds). Phrase structure and the lexicon. Dordrecht, Kluwer, pp. 109-137Google Scholar
  25. Kratzer A. (1998). More structural analogies between pronouns and tenses. In: Strolovitch D., Lawson A. (eds) Proceedings of SALT 8. Ithaca NY, CLC Publications, pp. 92–110Google Scholar
  26. Krifka M. (1998). Additive particles under stress. In: Strolovitch D., Lawson A. (eds) Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory 8. Ithaca NY, CLC Publications, pp. 111–128Google Scholar
  27. Krifka, M. (2000). Alternatives for aspectual particles: Semantics of still and already. Paper presented at the Berkeley Linguistics Society, February 2000.Google Scholar
  28. Kripke, S. (1990). Presupposition and anaphora: Remarks on the formulation of the projection problem. Ms., Princeton University.Google Scholar
  29. Lasersohn P. (1999). Parts, wholes, and still. Studies in the Linguistic Sciences, 29(1): 81–86Google Scholar
  30. Lewis D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge Mass, Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
  31. Löbner S. (1989). German it schon - erst - noch: An integrated analysis. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12: 167–212CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. McCawley J. (1981). Everything that linguists have always wanted to know about logic but were ashamed to ask. Chicago, The University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
  33. Merchant J. (2004). Fragments and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy, 27(6): 661–738CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Michaelis L. (1993). ‘Continuity’ within three scalar models: The polysemy of adverbial still. Journal of Semantics, 10: 193–237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Mittwoch A. (1993). The relationship between schon/already and noch/still: A reply to Löbner. Natural Language Semantics, 2: 71–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Pesetsky D. (2000). Phrasal movement and its kin. Cambridge Mass, MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  37. Potts C. (2005). The logic of conventional implicature. Oxford, Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  38. Rooij, V. R., & Schulz, K. (2005). Only: Meaning and implicatures. Manuscript, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  39. Rooth M. (1985). Association with focus. Amherst Mass, GLSA PublicationsGoogle Scholar
  40. Soames, S. (1989). Presupposition. In D. Gabbayz & F. Guenthnet (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 4, pp. 553–617). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  41. Stalnaker R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2: 447–457CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Stalnaker R. (1974) Pragmatic presuppositions. In: Munitz M., Unger P.(eds). Semantics and philosophy. New York, New York University Press, pp. 197-213Google Scholar
  43. Von Stechow A. (1984). Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics, 3: 1–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Von Stechow A. (1990). Focusing and backgrounding operators. In: Werner A. (eds). Discourse particles. Amsterdam, John Benjamins, pp. 37-84Google Scholar
  45. Von Stechow A. (1996). The different readings of wieder ‘again’: A structural account. Journal of Semantics, 13: 87–138CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of LinguisticsUniversity of TorontoTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations