Advertisement

Natural Language Semantics

, Volume 14, Issue 3, pp 257–281 | Cite as

Generic one, arbitrary PRO, and the first person

  • Friederike Moltmann
Original Paper

Abstract

The generic pronoun one (or its empty counterpart, arbitrary PRO) exhibits a range of properties that show a special connection to the first person, or rather the relevant intentional agent (speaker, addressee, or described agent). Generic one typically leads to generic sentences whose generalization is obtained from a first-person experience or action or else is meant to be immediately applicable to the relevant agent himself (in particular the addressee). I will argue that generic one involves generic quantification in which the predicate is applied to a given entity ‘as if’ to the relevant agent himself. This is best understood in terms of simulation, a central notion in some recent developments in the philosophy of mind and cognitive science (Simulation Theory). generic one involves ‘generic simulation’, roughly ‘putting oneself into the shoes of anyone meeting relevant conditions. Formally, this means that generic one introduces a complex variable, consisting of an ordinary variable and a ‘mode of presentation’ of the relevant intentional agent, namely the property of being identical to that agent. Generic one, like other pronouns acting as bound variables, may also introduce just an ordinary variable. In both cases, the ordinary variable needs to be bound by a sentential generic operator.

Keywords

Noun Phrase Propositional Attitude Semantic Context Simulation Theory Intentional Agent 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Carlson G. (1995). Truth-conditions of generic sentences: Two Contrasting views. In: Carlson G.N., Pelietier F.J. (eds). The generic book. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 224-237Google Scholar
  2. Castaneda H.-N. (1966). He*: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio, 8, 130-157Google Scholar
  3. Castaneda H.-N. (1967). The logic of self-attributions to others. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 85-100Google Scholar
  4. Chierchia G. (1990). Anaphora and attitudes De Se. In: Bartsch R et al. (eds). Language in action. Foris Publications, Dordrecht, pp. 1-31Google Scholar
  5. Chierchia G. (1995). The variability of impersonal subjects. In: Bach E et al. (eds). Quantification in natural language. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp. 107-143Google Scholar
  6. Chomsky N. (1980). On binding. Linguistic Inquiry 11(1): 1-46Google Scholar
  7. Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  8. Cohen A. (1999). On the generic use of indefinite singulars. Journal of Semantics, 18(3):183-209CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Davies M., Stone T. (eds). (1995). Mental simulation, Evaluations and applications. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  10. Evans G. (1982). Self-identification. In: McDowell Y (eds). Varieties of reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 205-233Google Scholar
  11. Fodor J. (1975). The language of thought. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NYGoogle Scholar
  12. Forbes G. (1997). How much substitutivity? Analysis, 57(2):109-113Google Scholar
  13. Gaerdenfors P. (1986). Belief revision and the Ramsey test for conditionals. Philosophical Review, 95:81-93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Giorgi A., Longobardi P. (1991). The syntax of noun phrases: Configuration, parameters, and empty categories. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  15. Goldman A.I. (1989). Interpretation psychologized. Mind and Language, 4:161-185CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Goldman, A.I (1995). In defense of simulation theory. In M. Davies , & T. Stone (Eds.), Mental simulation: Evaluation and applications. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  17. Gordon R.M. (1986). Folkpsychology as simulation. Mind and Language, 1, 158-171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gordon, R. M. (1995a). The simulation theory: Objections and misconceptions. In M. M. Davies, & T. Stone (Eds.), Mental simulation: Evaluation and applications. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Gordon, R. M. (1995b). Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you. In M. Davies, & T. Stone (Eds.).Google Scholar
  20. Heal, J. (1986). Replication and functionalism. In J. Butterfield (Ed.), Language, mind, and logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Heim, I. (1982). The semantics and definite and indefinite noun phrases. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
  22. Higginbotham, J. (2003). Remembering, imagining, and the first person. In A. Barber (Ed.), Epistemology of language (pp. 496-533). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Kadmon N., Landman F. (1993) Any. Linguistics and Philosophy, 16:355-422CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kamp H. (1981). A theory of truth and representation. In: Groenendijk J et al. (eds). Truth interpretation and information. Dordrecht, Foris, pp. 277-322Google Scholar
  25. Kratzer, A. (1998). More structural analogies between pronouns and tense. In D. Strolovitds, & A. Lawson (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 8 (pp. 92-110). Thaca, NY: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  26. Kratzer, A. (2006). Indefinites and the operators they depend on: From Japanese to Salish. In G. N. Carlson, & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), Reference and quantification. The partee effect. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  27. Krifka, M., et al. (1995). Genericity. An introduction. In G. V. Carlson, & F. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Lasnik H. (1981). On two recent treatments of disjoined reference. Journal of Linguistic Research, 1(4):48-58Google Scholar
  29. Lewis D. (1975). Adverbs of quantification. In: Keenan E (eds). Formal semantics of natural language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 3-15Google Scholar
  30. Lewis D. (1979). Attitudes De Dicto and De Se. The Philosophical Review, 88, 513-543CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Perry, J. (1996). The self. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  32. Ramsey, F. P. (1931). General propositions and causality. In The foundations of mathematics (pp. 237-255). London: Routledge and Kegan.Google Scholar
  33. Recanati F. (2002). Varieties of simulation. In: Dokic J., Proust J (eds). Simulation and knowledge of action. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 151-171Google Scholar
  34. Rosenthal, D. (2003). Unity of consciousness and the self. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 23(3), 325-352.Google Scholar
  35. Safir K. (2000). Keeping one’s reference constant. Manuscript, Rutgers UniversityGoogle Scholar
  36. Saul J. (1997). Substitution and simple sentences. Analysis, 57(2):102-108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Shoemaker S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy, 65(19):555-567CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.IHPSTParisFrance

Personalised recommendations