Minds and Machines

, Volume 22, Issue 4, pp 353–380 | Cite as

The Explanatory Role of Computation in Cognitive Science

Article

Abstract

Which notion of computation (if any) is essential for explaining cognition? Five answers to this question are discussed in the paper. (1) The classicist answer: symbolic (digital) computation is required for explaining cognition; (2) The broad digital computationalist answer: digital computation broadly construed is required for explaining cognition; (3) The connectionist answer: sub-symbolic computation is required for explaining cognition; (4) The computational neuroscientist answer: neural computation (that, strictly, is neither digital nor analogue) is required for explaining cognition; (5) The extreme dynamicist answer: computation is not required for explaining cognition. The first four answers are only accurate to a first approximation. But the “devil” is in the details. The last answer cashes in on the parenthetical “if any” in the question above. The classicist argues that cognition is symbolic computation. But digital computationalism need not be equated with classicism. Indeed, computationalism can, in principle, range from digital (and analogue) computationalism through (the weaker thesis of) generic computationalism to (the even weaker thesis of) digital (or analogue) pancomputationalism. Connectionism, which has traditionally been criticised by classicists for being non-computational, can be plausibly construed as being either analogue or digital computationalism (depending on the type of connectionist networks used). Computational neuroscience invokes the notion of neural computation that may (possibly) be interpreted as a sui generis type of computation. The extreme dynamicist argues that the time has come for a post-computational cognitive science. This paper is an attempt to shed some light on this debate by examining various conceptions and misconceptions of (particularly digital) computation.

Keywords

Computation Connectionism Dynamicism Computationalism Classicism Computational neuroscience Cognitive science Mechanistic explanation Representation 

References

  1. Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bechtel, W. (1998a). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22, 295–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bechtel, W. (1998b). Dynamicists versus computationalists: Whither mechanists? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 629.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bechtel, W. (2001). Representations: From neural systems to cognitive systems. In W. Bechtel, P. Mandik, J. Mundale, & R. S. Stufflebeam (Eds.), Philosophy and the neurosciences: A reader. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  5. Bechtel, W. (2009). Constructing a philosophy of science of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 548–569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2002). Connectionism and the mind: Parallel processing, dynamics, and evolution in networks (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  7. Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research (2nd ed.). Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  8. Beer, R. (forthcoming). Dynamical systems and embedded cognition. In K. Frankish and W. Ramsey (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Boden, M. A. (2008). Information, computation, and cognitive science. In P. Adriaans and J. van Benthem (Eds.). Handbook of the philosophy of science, volume 8: Philosophy of information, pp. 741–761. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  10. Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Burks A. W., Goldstine, H. H., & von Neumann, J. (1946). Preliminary discussion of the logical design of an electronic computing instrument. In B. Randell (Ed.), The origins of digital computers: Selected papers. (3rd ed. 1982). pp. 399–414. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  12. Chalmers, D. (1992). Subsymbolic computation and the Chinese room. In J. Dinsmore (Ed.), The symbolic and connectionist paradigms: Closing the gap (pp. 25–47). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  13. Chalmers, D. (1993). Why Fodor and Pylyshyn were wrong: The simplest refutation. Philosophical Psychology, 6, 305–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Chomsky, N. (1992). Language and interpretation: Philosophical reflections and empirical Inquiry. In J. Earman (Ed.), Inference, explanation, and other frustrations: Essays in the philosophy of Science (pp. 99–128). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  15. Churchland, P. S., Koch, C., & Senjowsky, T. J. (1988). What is computational neuroscience? In E. L. Schwartz (Ed.), Computational neuroscience (pp. 46–55). Cambridge, MA: The MIT press.Google Scholar
  16. Churchland, P. S., & Senjowsky, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Clark, A. (1990). Connectionism, competence, and explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 41, 195–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Copeland, B. J. (1996). What is computation? Synthese, 108, 335–359.MathSciNetMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Copeland, B. J. (1997). The broad conception of computation. The American Behavioral Scientist, 40, 690–716.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2006). Mechanism. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), Philosophy of science: An encyclopedia (pp. 469–478). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  21. Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Dayan, P., & Abbott, L. F. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience: Computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. New York: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
  24. Diederich, J. (1990). Spreading activation and connectionist models for natural language processing. Theoretical Linguistics, 16, 25–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Dodig-Crnkovic, G., & Burgin, M. (2011). Information and computation: Essays on scientific and philosophical understanding of foundations of information and computation. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company.MATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Dreyfus, H. (1972). What computers can’t do. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
  27. Egan, F. (2011). Two kinds of representational contents for cognitive theorizing. Paper presented at the 2011 Philosophy and the Brain conference at the Institute for Advanced Studies, Hebrew University in Jerusalem, Israel. Retrieved May 9, 2011, from https://sites.google.com/site/philosophybrainias2011/home/conference-papers-1/Egan-TwoKindsofRepContent.pdf?attredirects=0&d=1.
  28. Eliasmith, C. (2003). Moving beyond metaphors: Understanding the mind for what it is. The Journal of Philosophy, 100, 493–520.Google Scholar
  29. Eliasmith, C. (2007). Computational neuroscience. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science: Handbook of philosophy of science. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  30. Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, representation and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  31. Fodor, J. A. (1980). Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognition psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 63–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Fodor, J. A. (1981). The mind-body problem. Scientific American, 244, 114–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Fresco, N. (2010). A computational account of connectionist networks. Recent Patents on Computer Science, 3, 20–27.Google Scholar
  35. Froese, T. (2011). Breathing new life into cognitive science. Avant, 2, 113–129.Google Scholar
  36. Gandy, R. (1980). Church’s thesis and principles for mechanisms. In J. Barwise, H. J. Keisler, & K. Kunen (Eds.), The Kleene symposium (pp. 123–148). Amsterdam: North-Holland.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Hamann, H., & Wörn, H. (2007). Embodied computation. Parallel Processing Letters, 17, 287–298.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Haugeland, J. (1985). AI: The very idea. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  39. Horst, S. (1999). Symbols and computation: A critique of the computational theory of mind. Minds and Machines, 9, 347–381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Izhikevich, E. M. (2007). Dynamical systems in neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  41. Kaplan, D. M., & Bechtel, W. (2011). Dynamical models: An alternative or complement to mechanistic explanations? Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 438–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Kremer, S. C. (2007). Spatio-temporal connectionist networks. In P. A. Fishwick (Ed.), Handbook of dynamic system modelling. London: Chapman & Hall/CRC.Google Scholar
  43. Maass, W., & Markram, H. (2004). On the computational power of circuits of spiking neurons. Journal of Computer and System Sciences, 69, 593–616.MathSciNetMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, 27–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. MacLennan, B. J. (2001). Connectionist approaches. In N. J. Smelser & P. B. Baltes (Eds.), International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences (pp. 2568–2573). Oxford: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. MacLennan, B. J. (2004). Natural computation and non-Turing models of computation. Theoretical Computer Science, 317, 115–145.MathSciNetMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: W. H. Freeman & Co.Google Scholar
  48. Matthews, R. (1997). Can connectionists explain systematicity? Mind and Language, 12, 154–177.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biology, 5, 115–133.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  50. Newell, A. (1980). Physical symbol systems. Cognitive Science, 4, 135–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1976). Computer science as an empirical enquiry: Symbols and search. Communications of the ACM, 19, 113–126.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. O’Brien, G. (1999). Connectionism, analogicity and mental content. Acta Analytica, 22, 111–131.Google Scholar
  53. O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2006). How do connectionist networks compute? Cognitive Processing, 7, 30–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Pfeiffer, R., & Scheier, C. (1999). Understanding intelligence. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  55. Piccinini, G. (2008a). Computation without representation. Philosophical Studies, 137, 205–241.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Piccinini, G. (2008b). Computers. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89, 32–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Piccinini, G. (2008c). Some neural networks compute, others don’t. Neural Networks, 21, 311–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Piccinini, G., & Bahar, S. (2011). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Paper presented at the Computation and the Brain workshop 2011 at the Institute for Advanced Studies, Hebrew University in Jerusalem, Israel. Retrieved June 2, 2011, from https://sites.google.com/site/iascomputationbrainhuji2011/home/previous-lectures/Piccinini%26Bahar_NeuralComputationandtheComputationalTheoryofCognition.doc?attredirects=0&d=1.
  59. Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. F. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Piccinini, G., & Scarantino, A. (2011). Information processing, computation and cognition. Journal of Biological Physics, 37, 1–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Poggio, T., & Koch, C. (1985). Ill-posed problems in early vision: From computational theory to analogue networks. In the proceedings of the Royal Society of London, series B, Biological Sciences, 226, 303–323.MATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  63. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  64. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1993). Computers and the symbolization of knowledge. In R. Morelli, W. M. Brown, D. Anselmi, K. Haberlandt, & D. Lloyd (Eds.), Minds brains and computers: Perspectives in cognitive science and artificial intelligence. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.Google Scholar
  65. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1999). What’s in your mind? In E. Lepore & Z. W. Pylyshyn (Eds.), What is cognitive science? (pp. 1–25). MA: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
  66. Rubel, L. A. (1985). The brain as an analog computer. Journal of Theoretical Neurobiology, 4, 73–81.Google Scholar
  67. Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  68. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  69. Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Searle, J. R. (1990). Is the brain a digital computer? Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 64, 21–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Siegelmann, H. T. (1999). Neural networks and analogue computation: Beyond the Turing limit. Boston: Birkhauser.Google Scholar
  72. Siu, K. Y., Roychowdhury, V., & Kailath, T. (1995). Discrete neural computation: A theoretical foundation. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.MATHGoogle Scholar
  73. Smolensky, P. (1988). On the proper treatment of connectionism. The behavioural and brain sciences, 11, 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Smolensky, P. (1991). The constituent structure of connectionist mental states: A reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. In T. Horgan & J. L. Tienson (Eds.), Connectionism and the philosophy of mind (pp. 281–308). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Smolensky, P. (1995). Constituent structure and explanation in an integrated connectionist/symbolic cognitive architecture. In C. MacDonald & G. MacDonald (Eds.), Connectionism: Debates on psychological explanation (pp. 223–290). U.K.: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
  76. Smolensky, P., & Legendre, G. (2006). The harmonic mind: From neural computation to optimality-theoretic grammar. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  77. Spivey, M. (2007). The continuity of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  78. Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Stepp, N., Chemero, A., & Turvey, M. T. (2011). Philosophy for the rest of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 425–437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. Thagard, P. (2005). Mind: Introduction to cognitive science (2nd ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  81. Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamical systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press.Google Scholar
  82. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  83. Tienson, J. L. (1988). An introduction to connectionism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 26, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Trappenberg, T. (2010). Fundamentals of computational neuroscience (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.MATHGoogle Scholar
  85. van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. The behavioural and brain sciences, 21, 615–665.Google Scholar
  86. van Gelder, T., & Port, R. F. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In T. van Gelder & R. F. Port (Eds.), Mind as motion. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  87. Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  88. von Eckardt, B. (1993). What is cognitive science? Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  89. Wallace, B., Ross, A., Davies, J., & Anderson, T. (2007). The mind, the body and the world: Psychology after cognitivism?. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  90. Waltz, D. L., & Pollack, J. B. (1985). Massively parallel parsing: A strongly interactive model of natural language interpretation. Cognitive Science, 9, 51–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183, 313–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. White, G. (2011). Descartes among the robots: Computer science and the inner/outer distinction. Minds and Machines, 21, 179–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  93. Zednik, C. (2011). The nature of dynamical explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78, 238–263.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of History and PhilosophyUniversity of New South WalesSydneyAustralia

Personalised recommendations