Advertisement

Minds and Machines

, Volume 20, Issue 2, pp 277–289 | Cite as

Explanations in Software Engineering: The Pragmatic Point of View

  • Jan De Winter
Article

Abstract

This article reveals that explanatory practice in software engineering is in accordance with pragmatic explanatory pluralism, which states that explanations should at least partially be evaluated by their practical use. More specifically, I offer a defense of the idea that several explanation-types are legitimate in software engineering, and that the appropriateness of an explanation-type depends on (a) the engineer’s interests, and (b) the format of the explanation-seeking question he asks, with this format depending on his interests. This idea is defended by considering examples that are representative for explanatory practice in software engineering. Different kinds of technological explanation are spelled out, and the dependence of their appropriateness on interests and question-formats is extensively illustrated.

Keywords

Explanation Explanatory pluralism Explanatory power Epistemic interests Engineering 

Notes

Acknowledgments

This research was supported by subventions from the Research Foundation—Flanders through research project 3G003109. I am very grateful to Erik Weber and Jeroen Van Bouwel for helping me to improve this paper. Special thanks to Dries De Winter, for guiding me into the world of computer programming, and for reviewing this paper.

References

  1. De Langhe, R. (2009). Trading off explanatory virtues. In E. Weber, T. Libert, P. Marage, & G. Vanpaemel (Eds.), Logic, philosophy and history of science in Belgium. Proceedings of the young researchers days 2008. Brussels: Koninklijke Vlaamse Academie van België (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  2. De Ridder, J. (2007). Reconstructing design, explaining artifacts. Dissertation, University of Technology, Delft.Google Scholar
  3. Kroes, P. (1998). Technological explanations: The relation between structure and function of technological objects. Technè, 3(3), 18–34.Google Scholar
  4. Mackie, J. (1974). The cement of the universe: A study of causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  5. Pettit, P. (1996). The common mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Pitt, J. C. (2001). What engineers know. Techné, 5(3), 17–30.Google Scholar
  7. Radu, S. (2008). The Fisher-Yates shuffle algorithm. Paper presented at the mini conference on computing algorithms, Bryn Mawr.Google Scholar
  8. Tauro, T., & Kubota, A. (1999). A study on engineering history base. Research in Engineering Design, 11(1), 45–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Van Bouwel, J., & Weber, E. (2002). Remote causes, bad explanations. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 32(4), 437–449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Van Bouwel, J., & Weber, E. (2008). A pragmatist defense of non-relativistic explanatory pluralism in history and social science. History & Theory, 47(2), 168–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Weber, E. (1999). Unification: What is it, how do we reach it and why do we want it? Synthese, 118(3), 479–499.CrossRefMathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  13. Weber, E., & Van Bouwel, J. (2002). Symposium on explanations and social ontology 3: Can we dispense with structural explanations of social facts? Economics and Philosophy, 18(2), 261–277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Weber, E., Van Bouwel, J., & Vanderbeeken, R. (2005). Forms of causal explanation. Foundations of Science, 10(4), 437–454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Weber, E., & Vanderbeeken, R. (2005). The functions of intentional explanations of actions. Behavior and Philosophy, 33, 1–16.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Centre for Logic and Philosophy of ScienceGhent UniversityGhentBelgium

Personalised recommendations