Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy

, Volume 18, Issue 3, pp 421–431 | Cite as

Body matters: rethinking the ethical acceptability of non-beneficial clinical research with children

  • Eva De Clercq
  • Domnita Oana Badarau
  • Katharina M. Ruhe
  • Tenzin Wangmo
Scientific Contribution

Abstract

The involvement of children in non-beneficial clinical research is extremely important for improving pediatric care, but its ethical acceptability is still disputed. Therefore, various pro-research justifications have been proposed throughout the years. The present essay aims at contributing to the on-going discussion surrounding children’s participation in non-beneficial clinical research. Building on Wendler’s ‘contribution to a valuable project’ justification, but going beyond a risk/benefit analysis, it articulates a pro-research argument which appeals to a phenomenological view on the body and vulnerability. It is claimed that children’s bodies are not mere physical objects, but body-subjects due to which children, as persons, can contribute to research that may hold no direct clinical benefit to them even before they can give informed consent.

Keywords

Body Children Ethics Phenomenology Non-beneficial research Vulnerability 

References

  1. Ackerman, T.F. 1980. Moral duties of parents and nontherapeutic clinical research procedures involving children. Bioethics Quarterly 2(2): 94–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bartholome, W. 1976. Parens, children and the moral benefits of research. Hastings Center Report 6(6): 44–45.Google Scholar
  3. Beecher, H. 1966. Ethics and clinical research. New England Journal of Medicine 274: 1354–1360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 1979. Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Brock, D.W. 1994. Ethical issues in exposing children to risks in research. In Children as research subjects: Science, ethics and law, ed. M.A. Grodin, and L.H. Glantz, 81–102. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Brook, G. 2000. Children’s competency to consent: A framework for practice: In the first of two articles, Gill Brook introduces a framework of practice designed to help children to make choices in their treatment and care with their parents. Paediatric Care 12: 31–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Broström, L., and M. Johansson. 2014. Involving children in non-therapeutic research: on the development argument. Medical Health Care Philosophy 17: 53–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Burwood, S. 2008. The apparent truth of dualism and the uncanny body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7: 263–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Campbell, A.V. 2009. The body in bioethics. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  10. Carroll, T.M., and M.P. Gutmann. 2011. The limits of autonomy: The Belmont report and the history of childhood. Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Studies 66(1): 82–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Cavarero, A. 2009. Horrorism: Naming contemporary violence. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Coleman, C.H. 2009. Vulnerability as regulatory category in human subject research. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37(1): 12–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Curran, W.J., and H.K. Beecher. 1969. Experimentation in children. A reexamination of legal ethical principles. JAMA (Journal of the American Medical Association) 210: 77–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dickenson, D. 2007. Property in the body. Feminist perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Edwards, S.D. 2012. Safeguarding children in clinical research. Nursing Ethics 19(4): 530–537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fineman, M.A. 2008. The vulnerable subject: Anchoring equality in the human condition. Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 20(1): 1–23.Google Scholar
  17. Fingerson, L. 2011. Children’s Bodies. In The Palgrave handbook of childhood studies, ed. J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro, and M.-S. Honig, 217–227. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  18. Friedman Ross, L. 2003. Do Healthy children deserve greater protection in medical research. Journal of Pediatrics 142: 108–112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Friedman Ross, L. 2004. Children in medical research: Balancing protection and access: Has the pendulum swung too far? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 47(4): 519–536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Harris, J. 2005. Scientific research is a moral duty. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(4): 242–248.Google Scholar
  21. Hurst, S.A. 2008. Vulnerability in research and health care. Describing the elephant in the room? Bioethics 22(4): 191–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kipnis, K. 2003. Seven vulnerabilities in the pediatric research subject. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24(2): 107–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kottow, M. 2003. The vulnerable and the susceptible. Bioethics 17(5–6): 460–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kottow, M. 2005. Vulnerability: What kind of principle is it. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 7(3): 281–287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kodish, E. 2005. Ethics and research with children. A case-based approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Kopelman, L.M. 2004. Minimal risk as an international ethical standard in research. Journal of Medical Philosophy 29(3): 351–378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Leder, D. 1990. The absent body. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  28. Levine, C., R. Faden, C. Grady, D. Hammerschmidt, L. Eckenwiler, and J. Sugarman. 2004. The limitations of “vulnerability” as a protection of human research participants. The American Journal of Bioethics 4(3): 44–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Litton, P. 2008. Non-beneficial pediatric research and the best interest standard: A legal and ethical reconciliation. Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law and Ethics 359: 361–420.Google Scholar
  30. Litton, P. 2012. A more persuasive justification for pediatric research. American Journal of Bioethics 12(1): 44–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Luna, F. 2009. Elucidating the concept of vulnerability. Layers not labels. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2(1): 121–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Luna, F., and S. Vanderpoel. 2013. Not the usual suspects: Addressing layers of vulnerability. Bioethics 27(6): 325–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Mackenzie, C., and N. Stoljar. 2000. Introduction. Autonomy reconfigured. In Relational autonomy. Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency and the social self, ed. C. Mackenzie, and N. Stoljar, 3–31. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Mackenzie, C. 2010. Conceptions of the body and conceptions of autonomy in bioethics. In Feminist bioethics: At the center, on the margins, ed. J.L. Scully, L. Baldwin-Ragaven, and P. Fitzpatrick, 71–90. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  35. McCormick, R.A. 1976. Experimentation in children: Sharing in sociality. Hastings Center Report 6: 41–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Murray, T. 1996. The moral worth of a child. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  37. O’Neill, O. 2002. Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Petrăo Neves, M. 2009. Respect for human vulnerability and personal integrity. In UNESCO universal declaration on bioethics and human rights. Background, principles and application, ed. H.A.M. ten Have, and M.S. Jean, 155–164. Paris: UNESCO.Google Scholar
  39. Piasecki, J., M. Waligora and V. Dranseika. 2014. Non-beneficial pediatric research: Individual and social interests. Medical Health Care and Philosophy (Epub ahead of print).Google Scholar
  40. Ramsey, P. 1970. The patient as person: Explorations in medical ethics. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Rendtorff, J.D., and P. Kemp. 2000. Basic ethical principles in European bioethics and biolaw, autonomy, dignity, integrity and vulnerability, I–II ed. Barcelona/Copenhagen: Center for Ethics and Law.Google Scholar
  42. Resnik, D.B. 2005. Eliminating the daily life risks standard from the definition of minimal risk. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(1): 35–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Ricoeur, P. 1992. Oneself as another. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  44. Robinson, W. M. and B. T. Unruh. 2008. The hepatitis experiments at the Willowbrook state school. In The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics, ed. J. E. Ezekiel, 80-85. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Rogers, W., C. Mackenzie and S. Dodds. 2012. Why bioethics needs a concept of vulnerability. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics. Special issue on vulnerability 5(2): 11–38.Google Scholar
  46. Roth-Cline, M., J. Gerson, et al. 2011. Ethical considerations in conducting pediatric research. In Handbook of experimental pharmacology, vol. 205, ed. H. Seyberth, A. Rane, and M. Schwab, 219–244. Heidelberg/Dordrecht/London/New York: Springer Verlag.Google Scholar
  47. Schroeder, D., and E. Gefenas. 2009. Vulnerability: Too vague and too broad. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 18: 113–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Shah, S., A. Whittle, B. Wilfond, G. Gensler, and D. Wendler. 2004. How do institutional review boards apply the federal risk and benefit standards for pediatric research? Journal of the American Medical Association 291(4): 476–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Shah, S. 2013. Does research with children violate the best interest standard? An empirical and conceptual analysis. Northwestern Journal of Law and Social Policy 8(2): 121–173.Google Scholar
  50. Sharav, V.H. 2003. Children in clinical research: A conflict of moral values. The American Journal of Bioethics 3(1): 12–59.Google Scholar
  51. Shildrick, M., and R. Mykitiuk (eds.). 2005. Ethics of the body. Postconventional challenges. Massachusetts: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  52. Shirkey, H. 1968. Therapeutic orphans. Journal of Pediatrics 72(1): 119–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Thompson, P.B. 1990. Risk objectivism and risk subjectivism: When are risks real? Issues in Health and Safety 1: 3–22.Google Scholar
  54. Turner, B.S. 2006. Vulnerability and human rights. Pennsylvania: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Veatch, R.M. 1987. The Patients as partner. A theory of human experimentation ethics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Wachbroit, R. 2012. On Wendler’s new justification for pediatric research. The American Journal of Bioethics 12(1): 40–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Weisstub, D.N. 1998. Roles in clincal and research ethics. In Research on human subjects. Ethics, law and social policy, ed. D.N. Weisstub, 56–72. Oxford: Pergamon.Google Scholar
  58. Weisstub, D.N., S.N. Verdun-Jones, and J. Walker. 1998. Biomedical experimentation with children: Balancing the need for protective measures with the need to respect children’s developing ability to make significant life decisions for themselves. In Research on human subjects. Ethics, law and social policy, ed. D.N. Weisstub, 380–432. Oxford: Pergamon.Google Scholar
  59. Wendler, D. 2009. Minimal risk in pediatric research as a function of age. Archives of Pediatrics & Adolescent Medicine 163(2): 115–118.Google Scholar
  60. Wendler, D. 2010. The ethics of pediatric research. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Wendler, D. 2012. A new justification for pediatric research without the potential for clinical benefit. The American Journal of Bioethics 12(1): 23–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Wendler, D. 2013. Does U.S regulations allow for more than minor increase over minimal risk pediatric research? Should they? IRB: Ethics and Human Research 35(6): 1–8.Google Scholar
  63. Wendler, D., and S. Shah. 2003. Should children decide whether they are enrolled in nonbeneficial research? The American Journal of Bioethics 3(4): 1–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Whitty-Rogers, J., M. Alex, C. MacDonald, et al. 2009. Working with children in end-of-life decision-making. Nursing Ethics 16(6): 743–758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Williams, G. 2012. Children as means and ends in large-scale medical research. Bioethics 26(8): 422–430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Wolpe, R.W. 1998. The triumph of autonomy in american bioethics: A sociological view. In Bioethics and society: Constructing the ethical enterprise, ed. R. De Vries, and J. Subedi, 38–59. New York: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  • Eva De Clercq
    • 1
  • Domnita Oana Badarau
    • 1
  • Katharina M. Ruhe
    • 1
  • Tenzin Wangmo
    • 1
  1. 1.Institute for Biomedical EthicsUniversity of BaselBaselSwitzerland

Personalised recommendations