Advertisement

Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics

, Volume 40, Issue 3, pp 243–251 | Cite as

Pellegrino, MacIntyre, and the internal morality of clinical medicine

  • Xavier SymonsEmail author
Article

Abstract

There has been significant debate about whether the moral norms of medical practice arise from some feature or set of features internal to the discipline of medicine. In this article, I analyze Edmund Pellegrino’s conception of the internal morality of medicine, and situate it in the context of Alasdair MacIntyre’s influential account of “practice.” Building upon MacIntyre, Pellegrino argued that medicine is a social practice with its own unique goals—namely, the medical, human, and spiritual good of the patient—and that the moral norms that govern medical practice are derived from these goals. After providing an overview of Pellegrino’s work, I discuss some forceful objections to his theory—specifically, that it is too rigid and incapable of entering into dialogue with contemporary values systems; that it is dependent on an external conception of human flourishing; and that it is incompatible with the rapidly changing nature of modern medicine. In the final section of this article, I consider how theorists working in the Hippocratic tradition might respond to these objections against ethical essentialism by drawing upon MacIntyre’s historico-cultural method as well as what he calls Aristotle’s “metaphysical biology.”

Keywords

Ethics Natural law Metaethics Euthanasia Pluralism Edmund Pellegrino 

Notes

References

  1. 1.
    MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2007. After virtue: A study in moral theory, 3rd ed. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1999. Dependent rational animals: Why human beings need the virtues. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2001. The internal morality of clinical medicine: A paradigm for the ethics of the helping and healing professions. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26: 559–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Aristotle. 1984. Nicomachean ethics, trans. W.D. Ross. In The complete works of Aristotle, vol. 2, ed. Jonathan Barnes, 1729–1867. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2004. Philosophy of medicine and medical ethics: A phenomenological perspective. In Handbook of bioethics: Taking stock of the field from a philosophical perspective, ed. George Khushf, 183–202. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Pellegrino, Edmund D. 1999. The commodification of medical and health care: The moral consequences of a paradigm shift from a professional to a market ethic. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 24: 243–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Omelianchuk, Adam. 2018. Do you have a “syndrome” if you have a flat-shaped head? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 43: 369–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Miller, Franklin G., and Howard Brody. 2001. The internal morality of medicine: An evolutionary perspective. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26: 581–599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Veatch, Robert M. 2001. The impossibility of a morality internal to medicine. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26: 621–642.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Kenny, Nuala. 2006. Medicine’s malaise: The Pellegrino prescription. American Journal of Bioethics 6(2): 78–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Finnis, John. 2011. Natural law and natural rights, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for Ethics and SocietyUniversity of Notre Dame AustraliaBroadwayAustralia

Personalised recommendations