Advertisement

Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics

, Volume 31, Issue 1, pp 63–77 | Cite as

Schizophrenia, mental capacity, and rational suicide

  • Jeanette HewittEmail author
Article

Abstract

A diagnosis of schizophrenia is often taken to denote a state of global irrationality within the psychiatric paradigm, wherein psychotic phenomena are seen to equate with a lack of mental capacity. However, the little research that has been undertaken on mental capacity in psychiatric patients shows that people with schizophrenia are more likely to experience isolated, rather than constitutive, irrationality and are therefore not necessarily globally incapacitated. Rational suicide has not been accepted as a valid choice for people with schizophrenia due in part to a belief that characteristic irrationality prevents autonomous decision-making. Since people with schizophrenia are often seen to lack insight into the nature of their disorder, both psychiatric and ethical perspectives generally presume that suicidal acts result directly from mental illness itself and not from second-order desires. In this article, I challenge notions of global irrationality conferred by a diagnosis of schizophrenia and argue that, where delusional beliefs are unifocal, schizophrenia does not necessarily lead to a state of mental incapacity. I then attempt to show that people with schizophrenia can sometimes be rational with regard to suicide, where this decision stems from a realistic appraisal of psychological suffering.

Keywords

Mental capacity Rationality Schizophrenia Suicide 

References

  1. 1.
    Department of Health. 2005. Mental capacity act. London: HMSO.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Dimond, B. 2008. Legal aspects of nursing, 5th ed. Harlow: Pearson Education.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Department of Health. 1983. The mental health act. London: HMSO.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Department of Health. 2006. Mental health—written ministerial statement. March 23. DoH. Ref. No. 2006/0108.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Nordenfelt, L. 2007. Rationality and compulsion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Svavarsdottir, S. 2008. The virtue of practical rationality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1): 1–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Culver, C.M., and B. Gert. 1982. Philosophy in medicine: Conceptual and ethical issues in medicine and psychiatry. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Taylor, C. 1982. Rationality. In Rationality and relativism, ed. M. Hollis and S. Lukes, 87–105. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Guttenplan, S. 1999. A companion to the philosophy of mind. London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Fay, B. 1996. Contemporary philosophy of social science. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Lukes, S. 1970. Some problems about rationality. In Rationality, ed. B.R. Wilson, 194–213. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Graham, G. 1998. Philosophy of mind: An introduction, 2nd ed. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Frankfurt, H.G. 1971. Freedom of will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Radden, J. 1985. Madness and reason. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Edwards, R.B. 1982. Mental health as rational autonomy. In Psychiatry and ethics, ed. R.B. Edwards, 68–78. New York: Prometheus.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Bentall, R., P. Kinderman, and S. Kaney. 1994. The self, attributional processes and abnormal beliefs: Towards a model of persecutory delusions. Behaviour Research and Therapy 32 (3): 331–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    Peters, E., and P. Garety. 2006. Cognitive functioning in delusions: A longitudinal analysis. Behaviour Research and Therapy 44: 481–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Cholbi, M. 2009. Tonkens on the irrationality of the suicidally mentally ill. Journal of Applied Philosophy 26 (1): 102–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Cairns, R., C. Maddock, A. Buchanan, A. David, P. Hayward, G. Richardson, G. Szmukler, and M. Hotopf. 2005. Prevalence and predictors of mental incapacity in psychiatric in-patients. British Journal of Psychiatry 187: 379–385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Chiswick, D. 2005. Commentary: Test of capacity has little practical benefit. British Medical Journal 331: 1469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Nicholson, T., W. Cutter, and M. Hotopf. 2008. Assessing mental capacity: The mental capacity act. British Medical Journal 336: 322–325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Okai, D., G. Owen, H. McGuire, S. Singh, R. Churchill, and M. Hotopf. 2007. Mental capacity in psychiatric patients. British Journal of Psychiatry 191: 291–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Buchanan, A. 2004. Mental capacity, legal competence and consent to treatment. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 97: 415–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Mahler, B. 1992. Delusions: Contemporary etiological hypotheses. Psychiatric Annals 22: 260–268.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Kemp, R., S. Chua, P. McKenna, and A. David. 1997. Reasoning and delusions. British Journal of Psychiatry 170: 398–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 26.
    Owen, G., J. Cutting, and A. David. 2007. Are people with schizophrenia more logical than healthy volunteers? British Journal of Psychiatry 191: 453–454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Owen, G., G. Richardson, A. David, G. Szmukler, P. Hayward, and M. Hotopf. 2008. Mental capacity to make decisions on treatment in people admitted to psychiatric hospitals: Cross sectional study. British Medical Journal 337: 448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Bellhouse, J., A. Holland, I. Clare, M. Gunn, and P. Watson. 2003. Capacity-based mental health legislation and its impact on clinical practice: (2) Treatment in hospital. Journal of Mental Health Law July: 24–28.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Kim, S., P. Appelbaum, J. Swan, S. Stroup, J. McEvoy, D. Goff, D. Jeste, S. Lanberti, A. Leibovici, and E. Caine. 2007. Determining when impairment constitutes incapacity for informed consent in schizophrenia research. British Journal of Psychiatry 191: 38–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. 30.
    Doyal, L., and J. Sheather. 2005. Mental health legislation should respect decision making capacity. British Medical Journal 331: 1467–1469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Beauchamp, T., and J. Childress. 2001. Principles of biomedical ethics, 5th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Hewitt, J. 2007. Critical evaluation of the use of research tools in evaluating quality of life for people with schizophrenia. International Journal of Mental Health Nursing 16 (1): 2–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. 33.
    Hewitt, J. 2009. Rational suicide: Philosophical perspectives on schizophrenia. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13 (1): 25–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. 34.
    Werth, J.L. 1996. Rational suicide? Implications for mental health professionals. Washington: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Maris, R.W. 2002. Suicide. Lancet 360: 319–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    Drake, R., C. Gates, P. Cotton, and A. Whitaker. 1984. Suicide among schizophrenia: Who is at risk? Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 172: 613–617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Maltsberger, J. 1994. Calculated risk taking in the treatment of suicidal patients: Ethical and legal problems. Death Studies 18: 439–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. 38.
    Angermeyer, M.C., A. Holzinger, R. Kilian, and H. Matschinger. 2001. Quality of life as defined by schizophrenic patients and psychiatrists. International Journal of Social Psychiatry 47 (2): 34–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. 39.
    Bengtsson-Tops, A., and L. Hansson. 2001. Quantitative and qualitative aspects of the social network in schizophrenic patients living in the community: Relationship to sociodemographic characteristics and clinical factors and subjective quality of life. International Journal of Social Psychiatry 47 (3): 67–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Hasanah, C.I., and M.S. Razali. 2002. Quality of life: An assessment of the state of psychosocial rehabilitation of patients with schizophrenia in the community. Journal of the Royal Society of Health 122 (4): 251–255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. 41.
    Pinikahana, J., B. Happell, J. Hope, and N.A. Keks. 2002. Quality of life in schizophrenia: A review of the literature from 1995 to 2000. International Journal of Mental Health Nursing 11: 103–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    Beauchamp, T.L. 1986. Suicide. In Matters of life and death, 2nd ed, ed. T. Regan, 77–124. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
  43. 43.
    Siegel, K. 1986. Psychosocial aspects of rational suicide. American Journal of Psychotherapy 40: 405–418.Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    Brandt, R.B. 1992. Morality, utilitarianism and rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    Battin, M. 1994. The least worst death: Essays in bioethics on the end of life. New York: Open University Press.Google Scholar
  46. 46.
    Graber, G.C. 1998. Mastering the concept of suicide. In Suicide: Right or wrong? 2nd ed, ed. J. Donnelly, 150–161. New York: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
  47. 47.
    Kupfer, J. 1998. Suicide: Its nature and moral evaluation. In Suicide: Right or wrong? 2nd ed, ed. J. Donnelly, 162–174. New York: Prometheus.Google Scholar
  48. 48.
    Markova, I., and G. Berrios. 1992. The meaning of insight in clinical psychiatry. British Journal of Psychiatry 160: 850–860.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, History and Law, School of Human and Health SciencesSwansea UniversitySwanseaUK

Personalised recommendations