Advertisement

Continental Philosophy Review

, Volume 41, Issue 2, pp 127–142 | Cite as

The role of the lived-body in feeling

  • Bernhard Waldenfels
Article

Abstract

Feelings not only have a place, they also have a time. Today, one can speak of a multifaceted renaissance of feelings. This concerns philosophy itself, particularly, ethics. Every law-based morality comes up against its limits when morals cease to be only a question of legitimation and begin to be a question of motivation, since motives get no foothold without the feeling of self and feeling of the alien. As it is treated by various social theories and psychoanalysis, the self is not formed through the mere acquisition or change of roles, but rather through a process that is susceptible to crises, a process shaped by affective bonds and separations. Learning, which is the theme of pedagogy, loses its hold whenever it is confronted by disinterest and listlessness. In neurobiology, the increased significance of those zones of the brain that are connected with the realization of feelings makes the brain, accordingly, no mere apparatus that processes data, but a living organ that selects and “evaluates” what is “important.” Finally, cross-cultural comparison shows the extent to which the one-sided preference for understanding and willing, which is the mark of Western rationalism, arises from a typical, not to mention a highly masculine attitude toward the world and life, as many different studies on gender difference stress (In reference to this perspective, see Seethaler, Gefühle und Urteilskraft. Ein Plädoyer für die emotionale Vernunft, 1997). The following reflections provide a historical orientation directed toward a new determination of feelings. This new determination of feelings is phenomenological and takes the pathetic character of experience, nourished by the corporeality of experience as its point of departure.

Keywords

Feeling Affectivity Pathos Lived-body Phenomenology 

Notes

Translator’s Acknowledgements

I wish to express my deepest gratitude to Dr. Anthony Steinbock for all of his help in revising this translation. I would also like to thank Dr. Douglas Berger for his comments on an earlier draft of this translation.

References

  1. Descartes, René. 1951. Meditations on first philosophy (trans: Lafleur, L.J.). New Jersey: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  2. Emde, Robert N. ed. 1983. René A. Spitz: Dialogues from infancy, selected papers. New York: International Universities Press.Google Scholar
  3. Fink-Eitel, H., and G. Lohmann. ed. 1994. Zur Philosophie der Gefühle. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  4. von Goethe, Johann Wolfgang. 1961. Faust (trans: Kaufmann, W.). New York: Anchor Books.Google Scholar
  5. Goldstein, Kurt. 1934. Der Aufbau des Organismus. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  6. Grüny, Christian. 2004. Zerstörung der Erfahrung. Eine Phänomenologie des Schmerzes. Würzburg: Verlag Königshausen und Neumann.Google Scholar
  7. Hegel, G.W.F. 1977. Phenomenology of spirit (trans: Miller, A.V.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and time (trans: Macquarrie, J., and E. Robinson). New York: Harper and Row Publishers.Google Scholar
  9. Heine, Heinrich. 1976. Vorwort zu Geständnisse. In Sämtliche Schriften, Vol. 6/I. Carl Hanser: Munich.Google Scholar
  10. Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The crisis of European Sciences and transcendental phenomenology (trans: Carr, D.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Husserl, Edmund. 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, second book (trans: Rojcewicz, R., and A. Schuwer). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  12. Husserl, Edmund. 1999. Cartesian meditations (trans: Cairns, D.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  13. Husserl, Edmund. 2001. Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic (trans: Steinbock, A.J.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  14. Kant, Immanuel. 2003. The critique of pure reason (trans: Smith, N.K.). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  15. Kant, Immanuel. 2004. Prolegomena to any future metaphysics (translated and edited: Hatfield, G.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. van Kerckhoven, Guy. 2001. In Verlegenheit geraten. Die Befangenheit des Menschen als anthropologischer Leitfaden in Hans Lipps’ ‘Die menschliche Natur.’ In Revista de filosofía 26: 55–84.Google Scholar
  17. Kleist, Heinrich. 1952. Über die allmähliche Verfertigung der Gedanken beim Reden. In Sämtliche Werke. Munich: Helmut Sembdner.Google Scholar
  18. Libet, Benjamin. 2004. Mind time: The temporal factor in consciousness. Boston: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Lichtenburg, Georg Christoph. 1990. Aphorisms (trans: Hollingdale, R.J.). London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  20. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1962. Phenomenology of perception (trans: Smith, C.). New York. Routledge.Google Scholar
  21. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1989a. Beyond good and evil (trans: Kaufmann, W.). New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
  22. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1989b. On the genealogy of morals (trans: Kaufmann, W.). New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
  23. Ricœur, Paul. 2007. Freedom and nature: The voluntary and the involuntary (trans: Kohák, E.V.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Roth, Gerhard. 1997. Das Gehirn und seine Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  25. Scheler, Max. 1976. Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos. In Späte Schriften, Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 9. Bern/München: Francke Verlag.Google Scholar
  26. Scheler, Max. 1979. The nature of sympathy (trans: Heath, P.). London: Routledge and K. Paul.Google Scholar
  27. Scheler, Max. 2008. The human place in the Cosmos (trans: Frings, M.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press (in press).Google Scholar
  28. Seethaler, Carola Meier. 1997. Gefühle und Urteilskraft. Ein Plädoyer für die emotionale Vernunft. Munich: C.H. Beck.Google Scholar
  29. Sophocles. 1991. Antigone. In The oedipus plays of sophocles (trans: Roche, P.). New York: Mentor.Google Scholar
  30. Straus, Erwin. 1956. Vom Sinn der Sinne. Berlin/Göttingen/Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
  31. Thoma, Ludwig. 1962. Onkel Peppi und andere Erzählen. Munich: Paul List Verlag.Google Scholar
  32. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1994. Antwortregister. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  33. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1997. Wertqualitäten oder Erfahrungsansprüche? In Vom Umsturz der Werte in der modernen Gesellschaft, ed., G. Pafafferott. Bonn: Bouvier.Google Scholar
  34. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1998a. Der beunruhigte Blick. In Sinnesschwellen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  35. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1998b. Grenzen der Normalisierung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  36. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2002. Bruchlinen der Erfahrung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  37. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2004. Phänomenologie der Aufmerksamkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  38. Waldenfels, Bernhard, and Regula Giuliani. 2000. Das leibliche Selbst. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  • Bernhard Waldenfels
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of BochumBochumGermany

Personalised recommendations