Journal of Philosophical Logic

, Volume 40, Issue 2, pp 115–120 | Cite as

Notes on the History of Ideas Behind AGM

Article

Keywords

Belief revision AGM Theory change Conditionals Rationality postulates 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Alchourròn, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Alchourròn, C. E., & Makinson, D. (1981). Hierarchies of regulations and their logic. In R. Hilpinen (Ed.), New studies in Deontic logic (pp. 125–148). Reidel: Dordrecht.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Alchourròn, C. E., & Makinson, D. (1982). On the logic of theory change: contraction functions and their associated revision functions. Theoria, 48, 14–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Darwiche, A., & Pearl, J. (1997). On the logic of iterated belief revision. Artificial Intelligence, 89(1–2), 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Fagin, R., Ullman, J. D., & Vardi, M. Y. (1983). On the semantics of updates in databases. Proceedings of the Second ACM SIGACT SIGMOD Symposium on Principles of Database Systems (PODS'83), pp 352–365.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1979). Conditionals and changes of belief. In I. Niiniluoto & R. Tuomela (Eds.), The logic and epistemology of scientific change (pp. 381–404). Amsterdam: North Holland.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1980). A pragmatic approach to explanations. Philosophy of Science, 47, 404–423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1982a). Rules for rational changes of belief. In: T. Pauli (ed.), <320311>: Philosophical Essays Dedicated to Lennart Åqvist on His Fiftieth Birthday, Philosophical Studies published by the Phil. Society and The Dept. of Phil., Uppsala University, No. 34, Uppsala, pp 88–101.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1982). Imaging and conditionalization. Journal of Philosophy, 79, 747–760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1984). Epistemic importance and minimal changes of belief. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62, 136–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1986). Belief revisions and the Ramsey test for conditionals. Philosophical Review, 95, 81–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux: Modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. Cambridge: Bradford Books, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1994). Nonmonotonic inferences based on expectations. Artificial Intelligence, 65, 197–245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Gärdenfors, P., & Rott, H. (1995). Belief revision. In D. M. Gabbay, C. J. Hogger, & J. A. Robinson (Eds.), Handbook of logic in artificial intelligence and logic programming (Vol. 4, pp. 35–132). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 157–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Hansson, B. (1975). Explanations—of what? manuscript, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Hansson, S. O. (1992). A dyadic representation of belief. In P. Gärdenfors (Ed.), Belief revision (pp. 89–121). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Hansson, S. O. (1993). Theory contraction and base contraction unified. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 58, 602–625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Harper, W. L. (1977). “Rational conceptual change”, in PSA 1976, East Lansing. Mich: Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 462–494.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Harper, W. L. (1978). Bayesian learning models with revision of evidence. Philosophia, 7, 357–367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Katsuno, H., & Mendelzon, A. O. (1989). A unified view of propositional knowledge base updates, 2 Proceedings of the 11th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 269–276). San Mateo: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Levi, I. (1977). The enterprise of knowledge. Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Levi, I. (1991). The fixation of belief and its undoing: Changing beliefs through inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Makinson, D. (1987). On the status of the postulate of recovery and the logic of theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 16, 383–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    Makinson, D. (1996). In memoriam Carlos Eduardo Alchourrón. Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 3–10.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Makinson, D. (2003). Ways of doing logic: What was different about AGM 1985? Journal of Logic and Computation, 13, 5–15.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Makinson, D., & Gärdenfors, P. (1990). Relations between the logic of theory change and nonmonotonic logic. In A. Fuhrmann & M. Morreau (Eds.), The logic of theory change (pp. 185–205). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Ramsey, F. P. (1950). Foundations of mathematics and other logical essays. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Rott, H. (2001). Change, choice and inference: A study of belief revision and nonmonotonic reasoning. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions. In W. L. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change, and statistics (Vol. II, pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Lund University Cognitive ScienceLundSweden

Personalised recommendations