Advertisement

What the metasemantics of know is not

  • Peter van ElswykEmail author
Article

Abstract

Epistemic contextualism in the style of Lewis (in Aust J Philos 74:549–567, 1996) maintains that ascriptions of knowledge to a subject vary in truth with the alternatives that can be eliminated by the subject’s evidence in a context. Schaffer (in Philos Stud 119:73–103, 2004, in Oxford Stud Epistemol 1:235–271, 2005, in Philos Phenomenol Res 75:383–403, 2007, in Philos Issues 18(1):1–19, 2008, in: Schaffer, Loewer (eds) A companion to David Lewis, pp 473–490. Wiley, Hoboken, 2015), Schaffer and Knobe (in Noûs 46:675–708, 2012), and Schaffer and Szabó (in Philos Stud 168(2):491–543, 2014) hold that the question under discussion or qud always determines these alternatives in a context. This paper shows that the qud does not perform such a role for know and uses this result to draw a few lessons about the metasemantics of context-sensitivity.

Keywords

Epistemic contextualism Question under discussion qud Contrastivism Knowledge Metasemantics 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

References

  1. Anderbois, S., Brasoveanu, A., & Henderson, R. (2015). At-issue proposals and appositive impositions in discourse. Journal of Semantics, 32(1), 93–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beaver, D., & Clark, B. (2008). Sense and sensitivity: How focus determines meaning. Hoboken: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Blome-Tillmann, M. (2009). Knowledge and presuppositions. Mind, 118, 241–294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Frazier, L., Dillon, B., & Clifton, C. (2018). Together they stand: Interpreting not-at-issue content. Language and Speech, 62(2), 199–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Ginzburg, J. (1996). The semantics of interrogatives. In S. Lappin (Ed.), Handbook of logic and language (pp. 385–422). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Ginzburg, J. (2012). The interactive stance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Glanzberg, M. (2007). Context, content, and relativism. Philosophical Studies, 136, 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Glanzberg, M. (2013). Not all contextual parameters are alike. Manuscript: Northwestern University.Google Scholar
  10. Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1997). Questions. In J. van Benthem & A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (pp. 1055–1124). Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Hamblin, C. L. (1973). Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language, 10(1), 41–53.Google Scholar
  13. Hookway, C. (1996). Questions of context. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hunter, J., & Asher, N. (2016). Shapes of conversation and at-issue content. Semantics and Linguistics Theory, 26, 1022–1042.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ichikawa, J. (2011). Quantifiers and epistemic contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 155(3), 383–398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Ichikawa, J. (2015). Ignorance and presuppositions. Mind, 124(496), 1207–1219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Ichikawa, J. (2017). Contextualising Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kadmon, N., & Sevi, A. (2011). Without ’focus’. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6, 1–50.Google Scholar
  19. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almong, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. King, J. C. (2013). Supplementives, the coordination account and conflicting intentions. Philosophical Perspectives, 27(1), 288–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. King, J. C. (2014a). Speaker intentions in context. Noûs, 48(2), 219–237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. King, J. C. (2014b). The metasemantics of contextual sensitivity. In A. Burgess & B. Sherman (Eds.), Metasemantics: New essays on the foundations of meaning (pp. 97–118). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. McKenna, R. (2014). Normative scorekeeping. Synthese, 191(3), 607–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. McKenna, R. (2017). Conversational kinematics. In J. Ichikawa (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of epistemic contextualism (pp. 321–347). Abingdon on Thames: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Mion, G., & Gauker, C. (2017). The mind-independence of contexts for knowledge attributions. In J. Ichikawa (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of epistemic contextualism (pp. 455–464). Abingdon on Thames: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Montminy, M. (2013). The role of context in contextualism. Synthese, 190(12), 2341–2366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Morton, A. (2012). Contrastive knowledge. In M. Blaauw (Ed.), Philosophical explorations (pp. 74–89). Abingdon on Thames: Routledge.Google Scholar
  29. Murray, S. (2014). Varieties of update. Semantics and Pragmatics, 7, 1–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Roberts, C. (1996/2012). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics, 6, 1–69.Google Scholar
  31. Roberts, C. (2011). Only: A case study in projective meaning. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6, 1–59.Google Scholar
  32. Schaffer, J. (2004). From contextualism to contrastivism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 73–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive knowledge. Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 1, 235–271.Google Scholar
  34. Schaffer, J. (2007). Knowing the answer. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75, 383–403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Schaffer, J. (2008). Knowledge in the image of assertion. Philosophical Issues, 18(1), 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Schaffer, J. (2015). Lewis on knowledge. In J. Schaffer & B. Loewer (Eds.), A companion to David Lewis (pp. 473–490). Hoboken: Wiley.Google Scholar
  37. Schaffer, J., & Knobe, J. (2012). Contrastive knowledge surveyed. Noûs, 46, 675–708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Schaffer, J., & Szabó, Z. (2014). Epistemic comparativism: A contextualist semantics for knowledge ascriptions. Philosophical Studies, 168(2), 491–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Schoubye, A., & Stokke, A. (2016). What is said? Noûs, 50(4), 759–793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Simons, M., Tonhauser, J., Beaver, D., & Roberts, C. (2010). What projects and why. Proceedings of SALT, 20, 309–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Snider, T. (2017). At-issuness \(\ne \) anpahoric availability. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Society of American, 2(39), 1–15.Google Scholar
  42. Sosa, E. (1986). On knowledge and context. Journal of Philosophy, 83(10), 584–585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and Semantics (Vol. 9, pp. 315–332). Cambridge, MA: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  44. Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Stine, G. C. (1976). Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure. Philosophical Studies, 29, 249–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Stokke, A. (2010). Intention-sensitive semantics. Synthese, 175(3), 383–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Stokke, A. (2016). Lying and misleading in discourse. Philosophical Review, 125(1), 83–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Syrett, K., & Koev, T. (2015). Experimental evidence for the truth conditional contribution and shifting informational status of appositives. Journal of Semantics, 32(3), 525–577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Tonhauser, J. (2012). Diagnosing (not-)at-issue content. Proceedings of Semantics of Under-represented Languages of the Americas, 6, 239–254.Google Scholar
  50. van Elswyk, P. (forthcoming). Deceiving without answering. Philosophical Studies.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01239-7
  51. Williams, M. (2001). Contextualism, externalism and epistemic standards. Philosophical Studies, 103(1), 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentUniversity of Wisconsin-MilwaukeeMilwaukeeUSA

Personalised recommendations