Advertisement

A lot of hatred and a ton of desire: intensity in the mereology of mental states

  • Robert PasternakEmail author
Article
  • 24 Downloads

Abstract

Certain measurement-related constructions impose a requirement that the measure function used track the part-whole structure of the domain of measurement, so that a given entity or eventuality must have a larger measurement in the chosen dimension than any of its salient proper parts. I provide evidence from English and Chinese that these constructions can be used to measure the intensity of mental states like hatred and love, indicating that in the natural language ontology of such states, intensity correlates with part-whole structure. A natural language metaphysics of psychological intensity meeting this requirement is then developed and integrated into the semantics. Further complications arise when looking at attitudes like want, wish, and regret, which also permit measurements of intensity in the relevant constructions. To account for such attitudes, the ontology and semantics are then enriched in a way that integrates ordering and quantification over possible worlds into the part-whole structure of attitude states, so that even in these more complicated cases, the constructions at hand have a unified compositional semantics.

Keywords

Mental states Attitudes Measurement Event semantics Mereology Natural language metaphysics Comparatives Monotonicity 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

References

  1. Anand, P. & Hacquard, V. (2008). Epistemics with attitude. In T. Friedman & S. Ito (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 18, pp. 37–54). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.Google Scholar
  2. Anand, P., & Hacquard, V. (2013). Epistemics and attitudes. Semantics and Pragmatics, 6(8), 1–59.Google Scholar
  3. Asher, N. (1987). A typology for attitude verbs and their anaphoric properties. Linguistics and Philosophy, 10(2), 125–197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bach, E. (1986). Natural language metaphysics. In R. Barcan Marcus, G. J. W. Dorn, & P. Weingartner (Eds.), Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science VII (pp. 573–595). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  5. Bale, A., & Barner, D. (2009). The interpretation of functional heads: Using comparatives to explore the mass/count distinction. Journal of Semantics, 26(3), 217–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Beck, S. (2011). Comparison constructions. In K. von Heusinger, C. Maienborn, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 2, pp. 1341–1390). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  7. Beck, S., Oda, T., & Sugisaki, K. (2004). Parametric variation in the semantics of comparison: Japanese vs English. Journal of East Asian Linguistics, 13(4), 289–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bennett, M., & Partee, B. (1972). Toward the logic of tense and aspect in English. Santa Monica, CA: System Development Corporation.Google Scholar
  9. Brasoveanu, A. (2009). Measure noun polysemy and monotonicity: Evidence from Romanian pseudopartitives. In A. Schardl, M. Walkow & M. Abdurrahman (Eds.), Proceedings of the thirty-eighth conference of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS 38) (pp. 139–150). Amherst, MA: GLSA (Graduate Linguistic Student Association, University of Massachusetts).Google Scholar
  10. Büring, D. (2003). To want it is to want to be there: A note on Levinson (2003). UCLA, Los Angeles, CA, manuscript.Google Scholar
  11. Carlson, G. (1977). Reference to kinds in English. University of Massachusetts Amherst Ph.D. dissertation, Amherst, MA.Google Scholar
  12. Champollion, L. (2015). Stratified reference: The common core of distributivity, aspect and measurement. Theoretical Linguistics, 41(3–4), 109–149.Google Scholar
  13. Condoravdi, C. (2002). Temporal interpretation of modals: Modals for the present and for the past. In D. Beaver, L. Casillas, B. Clark, & S. Kaufmann (Eds.), The construction of meaning (pp. 59–88). Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  14. Condoravdi, C., & Lauer, S. (2016). Anankastic conditionals are just conditionals. Semantics & Pragmatics, 9(8), 1–69.Google Scholar
  15. Cresswell, M. J. (1976). The semantics of degree. In B. Partee (Ed.), Montague grammar (pp. 261–292). New York, NY: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Crnič, L. (2011). Getting even. MIT Ph.D. dissertation, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  17. Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action (pp. 81–95). Pittsburgh, PA: Pittsburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Erlewine, M. Y. (2007). A new syntax-semantics for the Mandarin bi comparative. Master’s thesis, University of Chicago.Google Scholar
  19. Erlewine, M. Y. (2017). Clausal comparison without degree abstraction in Mandarin Chinese. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, 36(2), 445–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Fara, D. G. (2013). Specifying desires. Noûs, 47(2), 250–272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Francez, I., & Koontz-Garboden, A. (2017). Semantics and morphosyntactic variation: Qualities and the grammar of property concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Heim, I. (1985). Notes on comparatives and related matters. Austin, TX: University of Texas at Austin.Google Scholar
  23. Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9(3), 183–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Heim, I. (2000). Degree operators and scope. In B. Jackson & T. Matthews (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 10, pp. 40–64). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.Google Scholar
  25. Hintikka, J. (1969). Semantics for propositional attitudes. In J. Hintikka (Ed.), Models for modalities (pp. 87–111). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Iatridou, S. (2000). The grammatical ingredients of counterfactuality. Linguistic Inquiry, 31(2), 231–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Jiang, L. J. (2009). Monotonicity and measure phrases in Chinese. Proceedings from the Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society, 45(1), 303–317.Google Scholar
  28. Kamp, H. (1975). Two theories about adjectives. In E. Keenan (Ed.), Formal semantics of natural language (pp. 123–155). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Katz, G., Portner, P., & Rubinstein, A. (2012). Ordering combination for modal comparison. In A. Chereches (Ed.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 22, pp. 488–507). Washington, DC: LSA.Google Scholar
  30. Kennedy, C. (1997). Projecting the adjective: The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison. University of California Santa Cruz Ph.D. dissertation, Santa Cruz, CA.Google Scholar
  31. Klecha, P. (2014). Bridging the divide: Scalarity and modality. University of Chicago Ph.D. dissertation, Chicago, IL.Google Scholar
  32. Klein, E. (1980). A semantics for positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4(1), 1–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Krantz, D., Luce, R. D., Suppes, P., & Tversky, A. (1971). Foundations of measurement, volume I: Additive and polynomial representations. New York, NY: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  34. Krasikova, S. (2008). Comparison in Chinese. In Bonami, O. & Cabredo Hofherr, P. (eds.), Empirical issues in syntax and semantics, (Vol. 7, pp. 263–281). http://www.cssp.cnrs.fr/eiss7/index_en.html
  35. Kratzer, A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In H. J. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (Eds.), Words, worlds, and contexts: New approaches in word semantics (pp. 38–74). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  36. Kratzer, A. (1991). Modality. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantik/semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 639–650). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  37. Kratzer, A. (1996). Severing the external argument from its verb. In J. Rooryck & L. Zaring (Eds.), Phrase structure and the Lexicon (pp. 109–137). Netherlands: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and conditionals: New and revised perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Krifka, M. (1989). Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics. In R. Bartsch, R. van Benthem, & Boas P. van Emde (Eds.), Semantics and contextual expression (pp. 75–115). Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
  40. Lassiter, D. (2011a). Measurement and modality: The scalar basis of modal semantics. New York University Ph.D. dissertation, New York, NY.Google Scholar
  41. Lassiter, D. (2011b). Nouwen’s puzzle and a scalar semantics for obligation, needs, and desires. In N. Ashton, A. Chereches, & D. Lutz (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 21, pp. 694–711). Washington, DC: LSA.Google Scholar
  42. Lassiter, D. (2017). Graded modality: Qualitative and quantitative perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Levinson, D. (2003). Probabilistic model-theoretic semantics for want. In R. Young & Y. Zhou (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 13, pp. 222–239). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.Google Scholar
  44. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  45. Lewis, D. (1981). Ordering semantics and premise semantics for counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10(2), 217–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Link, G. (1983). The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms. In R. Bäuerle, C. Shwarze, & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language (pp. 302–323). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  47. Liu, C.-S. L. (1996). A note on Chinese comparatives. Studies in the Linguistic Sciences, 26(1–2), 217–235.Google Scholar
  48. Moltmann, F. (2009). Degree structure as trope structure: A trope-based analysis of positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32(1), 51–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Nakanishi, K. (2007). Measurement in the nominal and verbal domains. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(2), 235–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Pasternak, R. (2016). A conservative theory of gradable modality. In M. Moroney, C.-R. Little, J. Collard, & D. Burgdorf (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 26, pp. 371–390). Washington, DC: LSA.Google Scholar
  51. Pasternak, R. (2018). The mereology of attitudes. Stony Brook University Ph.D. dissertation, Stony Brook, NY.Google Scholar
  52. Phillips-Brown, M. (2018). I want to, but.... In R. Truswell, C. Cummins, C. Heycock, B. Rabern & H. Rohde (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, (Vol. 21, pp. 951–968).Google Scholar
  53. Portner, P. (2009). Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Portner, P., & Rubinstein, A. (2016). Extreme and non-extreme deontic modals. In N. Charlow & M. Chrisman (Eds.), Deontic modality (pp. 256–282). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Reisinger, D. (2016). Ranked ordering sources and embedded modality. In P. Farrell (Ed.), Proceedings of The Linguistic Society of America (Vol. 36, pp. 1–12). Washington, DC: LSA.Google Scholar
  56. Rubinstein, A. (2012). Roots of modality. University of Massachusetts Amherst Ph.D. dissertation, Amherst, MA.Google Scholar
  57. Rubinstein, A. (2017). Straddling the line between attitude verbs and necessity modals. In A. Arregui, M. Luisa Rivero, & A. Salanova (Eds.), Modality across syntactic categories (pp. 610–633). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  58. Schwarzschild, R. (2002). The grammar of measurement. In B. Jackson (Ed.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) (Vol. 12, pp. 225–245). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.Google Scholar
  59. Schwarzschild, R. (2006). The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrases. Syntax, 9(1), 67–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in Logical Theories (American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series) (Vol. 2, pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  61. Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  63. Villalta, E. (2008). Mood and gradability: An investigation of the subjunctive mood in Spanish. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31(4), 467–522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. von Stechow, A. (1984). Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics, 3(1), 1–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. von Fintel, K. (1999). NPI licensing, Strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics, 16(2), 97–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2008). How to say ought in foreign: The composition of weak necessity modals. In J. Guéron & J. Lecarme (Eds.), Time and modality (pp. 115–141). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  67. Wellwood, A. (2014). Measuring predicates. University of Maryland Ph.D. dissertation, College Park, MD.Google Scholar
  68. Wellwood, A. (2015). On the semantics of comparison across categories. Linguistics and Philosophy, 38(1), 67–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Wellwood, A., Hacquard, V., & Pancheva, R. (2012). Measuring and comparing individuals and events. Journal of Semantics, 29(2), 207–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Xiang, M. (2003). A phrasal analysis of Chinese comparatives. Proceedings from the Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 39(1), 739–754.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Leibniz-Center for General Linguistics (ZAS)BerlinGermany

Personalised recommendations