Advertisement

Law and Philosophy

, Volume 37, Issue 4, pp 385–413 | Cite as

International Law, Institutional Moral Reasoning, and Secession

  • David LefkowitzEmail author
Article

Abstract

This paper argues for the superiority of international law’s existing ban on unilateral secession over its reform to include either a primary or remedial right to secession. I begin by defending the claim that secession is an inherently institutional concept, and that therefore we ought to employ institutional moral reasoning to defend or criticize specific proposals regarding a right to secede. I then respond to the objection that at present we lack the empirical evidence necessary to sustain any specific conclusion regarding an international legal right to secession. Specifically, I argue that we ought to adopt a precautionary approach, and that such an approach justifies giving no weight to promoting political self-determination per se when considering whether to reform international law governing secession. I conclude with several reasons to think that even a remedial right to unilateral secession will detract from, not enhance, the international legal order’s ability to promote peace and human rights.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Altman, Andrew and Christopher Heath Wellman, A Liberal Theory of International Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Anderson, Glen, ‘Secession in International Law and Relations: What are We Talking About?’, Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review 35 (2013): 343–388.Google Scholar
  3. Bederman, David J., International Law Frameworks, 2nd Edition (New York: Foundation Press, 2006).Google Scholar
  4. Bakke, Kristin M. and Erik Wibbels, ‘Diversity, Disparity, and Civil Conflict in Federal States’, World Politics 59 (2006): 1–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bellamy, Alex J. and Paul D. Williams, ‘On the Limits of Moral Hazard: The Responsibility to Protect, Armed Conflict, and Mass Atrocities’, European Journal of International Relations 18:3 (2012): 539–571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Berman, Paul Schiff, ‘Seeing Beyond the Limits of International Law’, Texas Law Review 84 (2006): 1265–1306.Google Scholar
  7. Brunnee, Jutta and Stephen J. Toope, ‘Constructivism and International Law’, in J. L. Dunoff and M. A. Pollack (eds.) Interdisciplinary Perspectives on International Law and International Relations: The State of the Art (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013).Google Scholar
  8. Buchanan, Allen, ‘Secession’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/secession/.
  9. Buchanan, Allen, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
  10. Copp, David, ‘International Law and Morality in the Theory of Secession’, Journal of Ethics, 2 (1998): 219–245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Craven, Matthew, ‘Statehood, Self-Determination, and Recognition’, in Malcolm D. Evans (ed.), International Law, 3rd Edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), pp. 203–251.Google Scholar
  12. Crawford, James R., The Creation of States in International Law, 2nd Edition (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 375–415.Google Scholar
  13. Fazal, Tanisha, ‘Is the Islamic State a Secessionist Movement?’, The International Relations and Security Network, February 20, 2015. http://www.isn.ethz.ch/Digital-Library/Articles/Detail/?id=188149; last accessed July 17, 2015.
  14. Ford, Richard T., ‘Law’s Territory: A History of Jurisdiction’, University of Michigan Law Review 97:4 (1999): 843–930.Google Scholar
  15. Gardiner, Stephen, ‘A Core Precautionary Principle’, Journal of Political Philosophy 14:1 (2006): 45–49.Google Scholar
  16. Horowitz, Donald, ‘A Right to Secede?’, in Stephen Macedo and Allen Buchanan (eds.), Secession and Self-Determination, NOMOS XLV (New York: New York University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
  17. Howse, Robert and Ruti Teitel, ‘Beyond Compliance: Rethinking Why International Law Really Matters’, Global Policy 1:2 (2010): 127–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kemoklidze, Nino, ‘The Kosovo Precedent and the ‘Moral Hazard’ of Secession’, Journal of International Law and International Relations 5:2 (2009): 117–140.Google Scholar
  19. Knight, Jack and James Johnson, The Priority of Democracy: The Political Consequences of Pragmatism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
  20. Kuperman, Alan J., ‘The Moral Hazard of Humanitarian Intervention: Lessons from the Balkans’, International Studies Quarterly 52:1 (2008): 49–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Lefkowitz, David, ‘Sources in Legal Positivist Theories: Law as Necessarily Posited and the Challenge of Customary Law Creation’, in Samantha Besson and Jean D’Aspremont (eds.), Oxford Handbook on the Sources of International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).Google Scholar
  22. Lefkowitz, David, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law’, in David Held and Pietro Maffettone (eds.), Global Political Theory (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016).Google Scholar
  23. Lefkowitz, David, ‘Reflections on the Thin Justice of International Law: Peace, Justice, and Secession’, Ethics and International Affairs Online, http://www.ethicsandinternationalaffairs.org/2015/reflections-on-the-thin-justice-of-international-law-peace-justice-and-secession-2/.
  24. Lefkowitz, David, ‘A New Philosophy for International Legal Skepticism? Dworkin, Republicanism, and the Rule of International Law’, unpublished manuscript on file with author.Google Scholar
  25. Miller, David, ‘Secession and the Principle of Nationality’, in M. Moore (ed.), National Self-Determination and Secession (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
  26. Moore, Margaret, The Ethics of Nationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Neff, Stephen C., Justice Among Nations: A History of International Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2014).Google Scholar
  28. Norman, Wayne, ‘The Ethics of Secession as the Regulation of Secessionist Politics’, in Margaret Moore (ed.), National Self- Determination and Secession (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998), pp. 34–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Postema, Gerald, ‘Custom, Normative Practice, and the Law’, Duke Law Journal 62 (2012): 707–738.Google Scholar
  30. Ratner, Steven R. The Thin Justice of International Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2003).Google Scholar
  32. Sambanis, Nicholas and Jonah Schulhofer-Wohl, ‘What’s in a Line?’, International Security 34:2 (2009): 82–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Shue, Henry, ‘Do We Need a Morality of War?’, in David Rodin and Henry Shue (eds.), Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 87–111.Google Scholar
  34. Sirosky David S., ‘Explaining Secession’, in Aleksandar Pavkovic and Peter Radan (eds.), The Ashgate Research Companion to Secession (Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, 2011).Google Scholar
  35. Weinstock, Daniel, ‘Constitutionalizing the Right to Secede’, The Journal of Political Philosophy 9:2 (2001): 182–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Wiens, David, ‘Prescribing Institutions Without Ideal Theory’, Journal of Political Philosophy 20:1 (2012): 45–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy Department, Program in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and Law (PPEL)University of RichmondRichmondUSA

Personalised recommendations