Advertisement

Specialisation and the Incommensurability Among Scientific Specialties

  • Vincenzo Politi
Article
  • 17 Downloads

Abstract

In his mature writings, Kuhn describes the process of specialisation as driven by a form of incommensurability, defined as a conceptual/linguistic barrier which promotes and guarantees the insularity of specialties. In this paper, we reject the idea that the incommensurability among scientific specialties is a linguistic barrier. We argue that the problem with Kuhn’s characterisation of the incommensurability among specialties is that he presupposes a rather abstract theory of semantic incommensurability, which he then tries to apply to his description of the process of specialisation. By contrast, this paper follows a different strategy: after criticising Kuhn’s view, it takes a further look at how new scientific specialties emerge. As a result, a different way of understanding incommensurability among specialties will be proposed.

Keywords

Specialisation Incommensurability Thomas Kuhn Scientific discovery 

Notes

Acknowledgements

This paper was written during a period of postdoctoral research at the Instituto de Investigaciones Filoso´ficas of UNAM (Mexico), under the supervision of Prof. Atocha Aliseda.

References

  1. Albert, D. (2000). Time and chance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Andersen, H. (2012). Conceptual development in interdisciplinary research. In U. Feest & F. Steinle (Eds.), Scientific concepts and conceptual change (pp. 271–292). Berlin: De Grutyer.Google Scholar
  3. Andersen, H. (2013a). Bridging disciplines. Conceptual development in interdisciplinary groups. In H. Frangerau, H. Geisler, T. Halling, & W. Martin (Eds.), Classification and evolution in biology, linguistics and the history of science. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.Google Scholar
  4. Andersen, H. (2013b). The second essential tension: On tradition and innovation in interdisciplinary research. Topoi, 32, 3–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Andersen, H. (2016). Collaboration, interdisciplinarity and the epistemology of contemporary science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 1–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Balmer, A., Bulpin, K., & Molyneux-Hodgson, S. (2016). Synthetic biology: A sociology of changing practices. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  7. Bechtel, W. (1986). Biochemistry: A cross-disciplinary endeavor that discovered a distinctive domain. In W. Bechtel (Ed.), Integrating scientific disciplines (pp. 77–100). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bechtel, W. (1993). Integrating sciences by creating new disciplines: The case of cell biology. Biology and Philosophy, 8, 277–299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bird, A. (2000). Thomas Kuhn. Chesham: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Bird, A. (2002). Kuhn’s wrong turning. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 33, 443–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Bird, A. (2003a). Kuhn, nominalism and empiricism. Philosophy of Science, 70, 690–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Bird, A. (2003b). Three conservative Kuhns. Social Epistemology, 17, 127–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Chang, H. (2013). Incommensurability: Revisiting the chemical revolution. In T. Arabatzis & V. Kindi (Eds.), Kuhn’s the structure of scientific revolutions revisited (pp. 153–178). Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
  14. Church, G. (2005). From systems biology to synthetic biology. Molecular System Biology.  https://doi.org/10.1038/msb4100007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Darden, L. (1978). Discoveries and the emergence of new fields in science. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association 1978, Vol. 1, pp 149–160.Google Scholar
  16. Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 44, 43–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Ereshefsky, M. (1998). Species pluralism and anti-realism. Philosophy of Science, 65, 103–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Feyerabend, P. (1962). Explanation, reduction and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space and time. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  19. Friedrich, K. (2013). Digital ‘faces’ of synthetic biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 150–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Frigg, R. (2008). A field guide to recent work on the foundations of statistical mechanics. In D. Rickles (Ed.), The Ashgate companion to contemporary philosophy of physics (pp. 99–195). Hampshire: Ashgate Publishing Limited.Google Scholar
  21. Gattei, S. (2008). Thomas Kuhn’s ‘linguistic turn’ and the legacy of logical empiricism. Hampshire: Ashgate Publishing.Google Scholar
  22. Gramelsberger, G. (2013). The simulation approach in synthetic biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 217–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hacking, I. (1993). Working in a new world: The taxonomic solution. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 275–310). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Hacking, I. (2007). Natural kinds: Rosy dawn, scholastic twilight. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 82, 203–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing scientific revolutions. Thomas Kuhn’s philosophy of science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  26. Hoyningen-Huene, P., & Oberheim, E. (2016). The incommensurability of scientific theories. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/incommensurability/. Accessed Jan 2018.
  27. Hoyningen-Huene, P., & Sankey, H. (Eds.). (2001). Incommensurability and related matters. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  28. Irzik, G., & Grünberg, T. (1998). Whorfian variations on Kantian themes: Kuhn’s linguistic turn. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 207–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Khalil, S., & Collins, J. (2010). Synthetic biology: Applications come to age. Nature Reviews Genetics, 11, 367–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2013). Basic science through engineering? Synthetic modelling and the idea of biology-inspired engineering. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 158–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Knuuttila, T., & Loettgers, A. (2014). Varieties of noise: Analogical reasoning in synthetic biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 48, 76–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kohler, R. (1971). The background to Eduard Buchner’s discovery of cell-free fermentation. Journal of the History of Biology, 4, 35–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kohler, R. (1972). The reception of Eduard Buchner’s discovery of cell-free fermentation. Journal of the History of Biology, 5, 327–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Kohler, R. (1973). The enzyme theory and the origin of biochemistry. Isis, 64, 181–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Kohler, R. (1975). The history of biochemistry: A survey. Journal of the History of Biology, 8, 275–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Kuhn, T. S. (1983). Commensurability, comparability, communicability. PSA1982, 669–688. Reprinted in Kuhn (2000), pp. 33–57.Google Scholar
  37. Kuhn, T. S. (1996/[1962]). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1st ed.: 1962; 2nd ed. with Postscript: 1970; 3rd ed.: 1996; 4th ed. with an introductory essay by Ian Hacking: 2012.Google Scholar
  38. Kuhn, T. S. (2000). The road since structure. Philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  39. Kühne, W. (1877). Über dans Verhalten verschiedener organisirter und sog. ungeformter Fermente. Verhandlungen des naturhistorisch-medicinischen Vereins zu Heidelberg, 1, 190–193.Google Scholar
  40. Marcum, J. (2015). The evolving notion and role of Kuhn’s incommensurability thesis. In W. Devlin & A. Bokulich (Eds.), Kuhn’s structure of scientific revolutions—50 years on. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  41. Massimi, M. (2015). ‘Working in a new world’: Kuhn, constructivism, and mind-dependence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 50, 83–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Masterman, M. (1970). The nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Proceedings of the international colloquium in the philosophy of science, London 1965 (pp. 59–89). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. McDonough, J. (2003). A Rosa Multiflora by any other name: Taxonomic incommensurability and scientific kinds. Synthese, 136, 337–358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. McMullin, E. (1993). Rationality and paradigm change in science. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 55–78). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  45. Patton, L. (2018). Kuhn, pedagogy, and practice: A local reading of structure. In M. Mizrahi (Ed.), The Kuhnian image of science: Time for a decisive transformation?. London: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  46. Payen, A., & Persoz, J. (1833). Mémoire sur la diastase, les principaux produits de ses réactions et leurs applications aux arts industriels. Annales de chimie et de physique, 53, 73–92.Google Scholar
  47. Politi, V. (2017). Specialisation, interdisciplinarity, and incommensurability. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 31, 301–317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Politi, V. (2018). Scientific revolutions, specialization and the discovery of the structure of DNA: Toward a new picture of the development of the sciences. Synthese, 195, 2267–2293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Richardson, A. (2002). Narrating the history of reason itself: Friedman, Kuhn, and a constitutive a priori for the twenty-first century. Perspectives on Science, 10, 253–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Roosth, S. (2017). Synthetic. How life got made. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Rouse, J. (2003). Kuhn’s philosophy of scientific practice. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Thomas Kuhn (pp. 101–121). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  52. Rouse, J. (2013). Recovering Thomas Kuhn. Topoi, 32, 59–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Ruphy, S. (2010). Are stellar kinds natural kinds? A challenge in the monism/pluralism and realism/anti-realism debate. Philosophy of Science, 77, 1109–1120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Shapere, D. (1966). Meaning and scientific change. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Mind and cosmos: Essays in contemporary science and philosophy (pp. 41–85). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  55. Sklar, L. (1993). Physics and chance. Philosophical issues in the foundations of statistical mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Steen, W. (1993). Towards disciplinary disintegration in biology. Biology and Philosophy, 8, 259–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Wray, K. B. (2011). Kuhn’s evolutionary social epistemology. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Instituto de Investigaciones FilosóficasMexicoMexico

Personalised recommendations