Advertisement

Journal for General Philosophy of Science

, Volume 48, Issue 2, pp 293–309 | Cite as

What is a Computer Simulation? A Review of a Passionate Debate

  • Nicole J. SaamEmail author
Report

Abstract

Where should computer simulations be located on the ‘usual methodological map’ (Galison 1996, 120) which distinguishes experiment from (mathematical) theory? Specifically, do simulations ultimately qualify as experiments or as thought experiments? Ever since Galison raised that question, a passionate debate has developed, pushing many issues to the forefront of discussions concerning the epistemology and methodology of computer simulation. This review article illuminates the positions in that debate, evaluates the discourse and gives an outlook on questions that have not yet been addressed.

Keywords

(Digital) computer simulation Thought experiments Experiments Play 

References

  1. Barberousse, A., Franceschelli, S., & Imbert, C. (2009). Computer simulations as experiments. Synthese, 169, 557–574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beisbart, C. (2011). A transformation of normal science. Computer simulations from a philosophical perspective. Unpublished habilitation thesis Technical University Dortmund.Google Scholar
  3. Beisbart, C. (2012). How can computer simulations produce new knowledge? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 395–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Beisbart, C., & Norton, J. D. (2012). Why monte carlo simulations are inferences and not experiments. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26, 403–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brown, J. R. (1991). The laboratory of the mind. Thought experiments in the natural sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  6. Brown, J. R. (2004). Why thought experiments transcend empiricism. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 23–43). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  7. Bryman, A. (2012). Social research methods (4th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Chandrasekharan, S., Subramanian, V., & Nersessian, N. J. (2013). Computational modeling: Is this the end of thought experimenting in science? In M. Frappier, L. Meynell, & J. R. Brown (Eds.), Thought experiments in philosophy, science and the arts (pp. 239–260). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. J. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cohnitz, D. (2006). Gedankenexperimente in der Philosophie. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  11. Coleman, J. S. (1964). Introduction to mathematical sociology. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  12. Cooper, R. (2005). Thought experiments. Metaphilosophy, 36, 328–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Crookall, D. (2011). Philosophy and simulation. Simulation & Gaming, 42, 146–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Di Paolo, E., Noble, J., & Bullock, S. (2000). Simulation models as opaque thought experiment. In M. A. Bedau, J. S. McCaskill, N. H. Packard, & S. Rasmussen (Eds.), Artificial life VII: The seventh international conference on the simulation and synthesis of living systems (pp. 497–506). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Dowling, D. (1999). Experimenting on theories. Science in Context, 12, 261–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Einstein, A. (1918–1921). Discussions of lectures in Bad Nauheim. In M. Janssen, R. Schulmann, J. Illy, C. Lehner, D. K. Buchwald (Eds.) (2002), The collected papers of Albert Einstein, Vol. 7: The Berlin Years: Writings (pp. 351–359). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  17. El Skaf, R., & Imbert, C. (2012). Unfolding in the empirical sciences: Experiments, thought experiments and computer simulations. Synthese, 190, 3451–3474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Elsenbroich, C., & Gilbert, N. (2014). Modelling norms. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fink, E., Saine, U., & Saine, T. (1968). The oasis of happiness: Toward an ontology of play. Yale French Studies, 41, 19–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Frigg, R. P., Hartmann, S., & Imbert, C. (Eds.) (2009). Models and simulations. Special issue. Synthese, 169, 425–626.Google Scholar
  21. Frigg, R. P., Hartmann, S., & Imbert, C. (Eds.) (2011). Models and simulations 2. Special issue. Synthese, 180, 1–77.Google Scholar
  22. Frigg, R., & Reiss, J. (2009). The philosophy of simulation: Hot new issues or some old stew? Synthese, 169, 593–613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Galison, P. (1996). Computer simulations and the trading zone. In P. Galison & D. J. Stump (Eds.), The disunity of science. Boundaries, contexts, and power (pp. 118–157). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Gilbert, N., & Troitzsch, K. G. (1999). Simulation for the social scientist. Buckingham: Mcgraw-Hill Professional.Google Scholar
  25. Gooding, D. (1990). Experiment and the making of meaning. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gramelsberger, G. (2006). Story telling with code-archaeology of climate modelling. TeamEthno-online, 2, 77–84.Google Scholar
  27. Gramelsberger, G. (2010). Computerexperimente. Zum Wandel der Wissenschaft im Zeitalter des Computers. Bielefeld: Transkript.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Gramelsberger, G. (2011). What do numerical (climate) models really represent? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42, 296–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009). The explanatory potential of artificial societies. Synthese, 169, 539–555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Grüne-Yanoff, T., & Weirich, P. (2010). The philosophy and epistemology of simulation. A review. Simulation & Gaming, 41, 20–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Guala, F. (2002). Models, simulations, and experiments. In L. Magnani & N. Nersessian (Eds.), Model-based reasoning: science, technology, values (pp. 59–74). New York: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: introductory topics in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Hacking, I. (1992). Do thought experiments have a life of their own? Comments on James Brown, Nancy Nersessian and David Gooding. In A. Fine, M. Forbes, & K. Okruhlik (Eds.), Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association 1992 (Vol. 2, pp. 302–338). East Lansing: The Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  34. Hartmann, S. (1996). The world as a process: Simulation in the natural and social sciences. In R. Hegselmann, U. Müller, & K. G. Troitzsch (Eds.), Modelling and simulation in the social sciences from the philosophy of science point of view (pp. 77–100). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Horowitz, T., & Massey, G. J. (Eds.) (1991). Thought experiments in science and philosophy. Savage: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  36. Humphreys, P. (1990). Computer simulations. In A. Fine, M. Forbes, & L. Wessels (Eds.), PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association 1990 (pp. 497–506). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  37. Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves. Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169, 615–626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Humphreys, P., & Imbert, C. (Eds.) (2012). Models, simulations and representations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  40. Knuuttila, T. (2006). From representation to production: Parsers and parsing in language technology. In J. Lenhard, G. Küppers, & T. Shinn (Eds.), Simulation: Pragmatic construction of reality (pp. 41–55). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Krohs, U. (2008). How digital computer simulations explain real-world processes. Internationals Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22, 277–292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Kuhn, T. S. (1964). A function for thought experiments. In M. A. Koyré (Ed.), L’Aventure de la science (Vol. 2). Paris: Hermann.Google Scholar
  43. Kuorikoski, J. (2012). Simulation and the sense of understanding. In P. Humphreys & C. Imbert (Eds.), Models, simulations and representations (pp. 168–187). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  44. Küppers, G., & Lenhard, J. (2005). Computersimulationen: Modellierungen 2. Ordnung. Journal for General Philosophy of Science/Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, 36, 305–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Lenhard, J. (2006). Surprised by a nanowire: Simulation, control, and understanding. Philosophy of Science, 73, 605–616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Lenhard, J. (2007). Computer simulation: The cooperation between experimenting and modeling. Philosophy of Science, 74, 176–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Lenhard, J. (2011). Epistemologie der Iteration. Gedankenexperimente und Simulationsexperimente. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 59, 131–145.Google Scholar
  48. Mach, E. (1960[1893]). The science of mechanics. Transl. by Thomas J. McCormack. Lasalle.: Open Court Publ. Co.Google Scholar
  49. Mach, E. (1976[1905]). Knowledge and error. Sketches on the psychology of enquiry. Transl. by Thomas J. McCormack and Paul Foulkes. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  50. MacLean, M., Russell, W., & Ryall, E. (Eds.) (2015). Philosophical perspectives on play. Routledge.Google Scholar
  51. McAllister, J. (1996). The evidential significance of thought experiment in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 27, 233–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Morgan, M. (2003). Experiments without material intervention. Model experiments, virtual experiments, and virtually experiments. In H. Radder (Ed.), The philosophy of scientific experimentation (pp. 216–235). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
  53. Morrison, M. (2009). Models, measurement, and computer simulation: The changing face of experimentation. Philosophical Studies, 143, 33–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Nersessian, N. J. (1992). In the theoretician’s laboratory: Thought experimenting as mental modeling. In Proceedings of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 2, pp. 291–301). The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  55. Norton, J. (1991). Thought experiments in Einstein’s work. In T. Horowitz & G. J. Massey (Eds.), Thought experiments in science and philosophy (pp. 129–148). Savage: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  56. Norton, J. (1996). Are thought experiments just what you thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 333–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Norton, S. D., & Suppe, F. (2001). Why atmospheric modeling is good science. In P. N. Edwards & C. A. Miller (Eds.), Changing the atmosphere (pp. 67–106). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  58. Ørsted, H. C. (1811). First introduction to general physics. In H. C. Ørsted (Ed.), Selected scientific works (pp. 282–309). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  59. Parker, W. S. (2009). Does matter really matter? Computer simulations, experiments, and materiality. Synthese, 169, 483–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Roux, S. (2011). Introduction: The emergence of the notion of thought experiments. In K. Ierodiakonou & S. Roux (Eds.), Thought experiments in methodological and historical contexts (pp. 1–33). Brill: Leiden.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Ryall, E., Russell, W., & MacLean, M. (Eds.) (2013). The philosophy of play. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  62. Sageng, J. R., Fossheim, H. J., & Larsen, T. M. (Eds.) (2012). The philosophy of computer games. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  63. Sorensen, R. A. (1992). Thought experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Sundberg, M. (2010). Cultures of simulations vs. cultures of calculations? The development of simulation practices in meteorology and astrophysics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41, 273–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Tal, E. (2011). From data to phenomena and back again: Computer-simulated signatures. Synthese, 182, 117–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Tymoczko, T. (1979). The four-color problem and its philosophical significance. Journal of Philosophy, 76, 57–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Winsberg, E. (2001). Simulations, models, and theories: Complex physical systems and their representation. Philosophy of Science, 68(Proceedings), S442–S454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Winsberg, E. (2003). Simulated experiments: Methodology for a virtual world. Philosophy of Science, 70, 105–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Winsberg, E. (2009). A tale of two methods. Synthese, 169, 575–592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Winsberg, E. (2010). Science in the age of computer simulation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Ziegler, R. (1972). Theorie und Modell. Der Beitrag der Formalisierung zur soziologischen Theoriebildung. München: Oldenbourg.Google Scholar
  72. Zimmermann, E. (1972). Das Experiment in den Sozialwissenschaften. Stuttgart: Teubner.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Friedrich-Alexander Universität Erlangen-NürnbergErlangenGermany

Personalised recommendations