Advertisement

Journal for General Philosophy of Science

, Volume 44, Issue 1, pp 111–125 | Cite as

Photographic Evidence and the Problem of Theory-Ladenness

  • Nicola MößnerEmail author
Article

Abstract

Scientists use visualisations of different kinds in a variety of ways in their scientific work. In the following article, we will take a closer look at the use of photographic pictures as scientific evidence. In accordance with Patrick Maynard’s thesis, photography will be regarded as a family of technologies serving different purposes in divergent contexts. One of these is its ability to detect certain phenomena. Nonetheless, with regard to the philosophical thesis of theory-ladenness of observation, we encounter certain reservations concerning the status of photography and that of photographic pictures in the process of measurement in science. Accordingly, the aim of this paper is twofold: We will discuss suggested solutions both for the technological and for the psychological part of the problem of theory-ladenness appearing in the context of the use of photography in scientific observations. The essential proposal will be to follow Christian Suhm in his advice to make a distinction between theory-relativity and theory-ladenness.

Keywords

Evidence Patrick Maynard Photography Scientific observation Technology Theory-ladenness 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Maria Reicher-Marek, Alexander Wagner and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper. This work was supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG) in the context of the project “Visualisierungen in den Wissenschaften – eine wissenschaftstheoretische Untersuchung”. For linguistic revision I thank Janet Carter-Sigglow.

References

  1. Abell, C. (2010). The epistemic value of photographs. In C. Abell & K. Bantinaki (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on depiction (pp. 81–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Carrier, M. (1994). The completeness of scientific theories. On the derivation of empirical indicators within a theoretical framework: The case of physical geometry. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  3. Chalmers, A. F. (1999). What is this thing called science? (3rd ed.). Buckingham: Open University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Davies, D. (2008). How photographs “signify”: Cartier-Bresson’s “reply” to Scruton. In S. Walden (Ed.), Photography and philosophy. Essays on the Pencil of Nature (pp. 167–186). Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
  5. Golan, T. (2002). Sichtbarkeit und Macht: Maschinen als Augenzeugen. In P. Geimer (Ed.), Ordnungen der Sichtbarkeit. Fotografie in Wissenschaft, Kunst und Technologie (pp. 171–210). Suhrkamp Verlag: Frankfurt/Main.Google Scholar
  6. Kosso, P. (1992). Reading the book of nature. An introduction to the philosophy of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Kuhn, T. S. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed.). Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Meskin, A., & Cohen, J. (2008). Photographs as evidence. In S. Walden (Ed.), Photography and Philosophy. Essays on the Pencil of Nature (pp. 70–90). Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
  9. Mitchell, W. J. (1994). The reconfigured eye. Visual truth in post-photographic era. Cambridge/London: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Maynard, P. (1989). Talbot’s technologies: Photographic depiction, detection, and reproduction. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 47(3), 263–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Maynard, P. (2000). The engine of visualization. Thinking through photography. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Maynard, P. (2010). Working light. Philosophy of Photography, 1(1), 29–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Perini, L. (2005a). The truth in pictures. Philosophy of Science, 72(01), 262–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Perini, L. (2005b). Visual representations and confirmation. Philosophy of Science, 72(05), 913–926.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ratzka, T. (2012). Die Fenster zum Himmel. In D. Liebsch & N. Mößner (Eds.), Visualisierung und Erkenntnis. Bildverstehen und Bildverwenden in Natur- und Geisteswissenschaften (pp. 237–264). Herbert von Halem Verlag: Cologne.Google Scholar
  16. Sachs-Hombach, K. (2006). Das Bild als kommunikatives Medium. Elemente einer allgemeinen Bildwissenschaft. Cologne: Herbert von Halem Verlag.Google Scholar
  17. Savedoff, B. (2008). Documentary authority and the art of photography. In S. Walden (Ed.), Photography and philosophy. Essays on the pencil of nature (pp. 111–137). Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
  18. Scholz, O. R. (2009). Bild, Darstellung, Zeichen. Philosophische Theorien bildlicher Darstellung (3rd ed.). Frankfurt/Main: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
  19. Scruton, R. (2008). Photography and representation. In S. Walden (Ed.), Photography and Philosophy. Essays on the Pencil of Nature (pp. 138–166). Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
  20. Suhm, C. (2005). Wissenschaftlicher Realismus. Eine Studie zur Realismus-Antirealismus-Debatte in der neueren Wissenschaftstheorie. Frankfurt/Lancaster: ontos Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Unsöld, A., & Baschek, B. (2005). Der neue Kosmos. Einführung in die Astronomie und Astrophysik (7th ed.). Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  22. Walden, S. (Ed.). (2008). Photography and Philosophy. Essays on the Pencil of Nature. Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
  23. Walton, K. L. (2008). Transparent pictures: On the nature of photographic realism. In S. Walden (Ed.), Photography and Philosophy. Essays on the Pencil of Nature (pp. 14–49). Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophisches InstitutRWTH AachenAachenGermany

Personalised recommendations