Journal for General Philosophy of Science

, Volume 42, Issue 1, pp 129–140 | Cite as

Carnap and Kuhn: On the Relation between the Logic of Science and the History of Science

Article

Abstract

This paper offers a refutation of J. C. Pinto de Oliveira’s recent critique of revisionist Carnap scholarship as giving undue weight to two brief letters to Kuhn expressing his interest in the latter’s work. First an argument is provided to show that Carnap and Kuhn are by no means divided by a radical mismatch of their conceptions of the rationality of science as supposedly evidenced by their stance towards the distinction of the contexts of discovery and justification. This is followed by an argument to the effect that the fact that Carnap’s own work concentrated on formal aspects of scientific theories does not licence the conclusion that he thought historical investigations and concerns irrelevant for what we nowadays would rightly call “philosophy of science”.

Keywords

Rudolf Carnap Distinction of contexts of discovery and justification History of science Thomas Kuhn Logical empiricism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

The author wishes to thank André Carus, William Demopoulos and two anonymous reviewers for their constructive criticisms.

References

  1. Axtell, G. (1993). In the tracks of the historicist movement: Re-assessing the Carnap-Kuhn connection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 24, 119–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Carnap, R. (1936). Von der Erkenntnistheorie zur Wissenschaftslogik. Actes du Congress Internationale de Philosophie Scientifique,Sorbonne, Paris 1935, Facs. I Philosophie Scientifique et Empirisme Logique, Paris: Herman & Cie, pp. 36–41.Google Scholar
  3. Carnap, R. (1938). Logical Foundations of the Unity of Science. In Otto Neurath et al., Encyclopedia and Unified Science (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science I/1), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 42–62.Google Scholar
  4. Carnap, R. (1949). “Truth and Confirmation”. In H. Feigl and W. Sellars (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 119–127, (Orig. 1936).Google Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  6. Carnap, R. (1963). Replies and expositions. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 859–1016). Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  7. Carnap, R. (1965). A few words to Philipp Frank, for the second volume of the Boston studies in the philosophy of science. In R. S. Cohen & M. Wartofsky (Eds.), In honor of Philipp Frank. Boston studies in the philosophy of science Vol. 2 (pp. xi–xii). New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
  8. Carnap, R. (1966). Philosophical foundations of physics. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  9. Carnap, R. (1968). Inductive logic and inductive intuition. In I. Lakatos (Ed.), The problem of inductive logic (pp. 258–267). Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
  10. Carnap, R. (1987). On Protocol Sentences, Nous 21, 457–470, (Orig. 1932).Google Scholar
  11. Carnap, R. (2002). The Logical Syntax of Language, Chicago: Open Court, (Orig. 1934).Google Scholar
  12. Carnap, R. (2003). The Logical Structure of the World, Chicago: Open Court, (Orig. 1928).Google Scholar
  13. Carnap, R., Hahn, H., & Neurath, O. (1973). Scientific World-Conception. The Vienna Circle. In O. Neurath. Empiricism and sociology (pp. 299–318) (M. Neurath & R. S. Cohen, Eds.), Dordrecht: Reidel, (Orig. 1929).Google Scholar
  14. Carus, A. (2007). Carnap and twentieth-century thought. Explication as enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Carus, A. (2010). The pragmatics of scientific knowledge. Howard Stein’s Reshaping of logical empiricism. The Monist 93.Google Scholar
  16. Earman, J. (1993). Carnap, Kuhn, and the philosophy of scientific methodology. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes. Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 9–36). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Frank, P. (1957). Philosophy of science. The link between science and philosophy. Engelwood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  18. Friedman, M. (1998). On the sociology of scientific knowledge and its philosophical agenda. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 239–271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Friedman, M. (2001). Dynamics of reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  20. Friedman, M. (2002). Kant, Kuhn, and the rationality of science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 171–190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Friedman, M. (2003). Kuhn and logical empiricism. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Thomas Kuhn (pp. 19–44). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Hempel, C. G. (2001). Scientific Rationality: Normative vs. Descriptive Construals. In The philosophy of C.G. Hempel (ed. by James Fetzer), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 357–371, (Orig. 1979).Google Scholar
  23. Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions. Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, (Orig. 1989).Google Scholar
  24. Irzik, G. (2003). Changing conceptions of the rationality of science: From logical positivism to post-positivism. In P. Parrini, M. Salmon, & W. Salmon (Eds.), Logical empiricism: Historical and systematic perspectives (pp. 325–346). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  25. Irzik, G., & Grünberg, T. (1995). Carnap and Kuhn: Arch enemies or close allies? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 285–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The Structure of scientific revolutions. (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science II/2) Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 2nd edn. 1970.Google Scholar
  27. Kuhn, T. S. (1970). Reflections on my critics. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 231–278). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment and theory choice. In Kuhn, The essential tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 320–339.Google Scholar
  29. Kuhn, T. S. (1993). Afterwords. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes. Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 311–342). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Neurath, O. (1983a). Sociology in the Framework of Physicalism. In Neurath, Philosophical Papers 19131946 (ed. by R.S. Cohen and M. Neurath), Dordrecht: Reidel, 58–90. (Orig. 1932).Google Scholar
  31. Neurath, O. (1983b). Physicalism and the Investigation of Knowledge. In Neurath, Philosophical Papers 19131946 (ed. by R.S. Cohen and M. Neurath), Dordrecht: Reidel, 159–166 and 168–171, (Orig. 1936).Google Scholar
  32. Pinto de Oliveira, J. C. (2007). Carnap, Kuhn, and revisionism: On the publication of Structure in encyclopedia. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 38, 147–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  34. Reisch, G. (1991). Did Kuhn kill logical empiricism? Philosophy of Science, 58, 264–277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Uebel, T. (2000). Logical empiricism and the sociology of knowledge. The case of Neurath and Frank. Philosophy of Science, 67, S138–S150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Uebel, T. (2007). Empiricism at the crossroads. The Vienna Circle’s protocol sentence debate. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy, School of Social SciencesThe University of ManchesterManchesterUK

Personalised recommendations