Advertisement

Husserl Studies

, Volume 34, Issue 1, pp 47–61 | Cite as

Brain, Mind, World: Predictive Coding, Neo-Kantianism, and Transcendental Idealism

  • Dan ZahaviEmail author
Article

Abstract

Recently, a number of neuroscientists and philosophers have taken the so-called predictive coding approach to support a form of radical neuro-representationalism, according to which the content of our conscious experiences is a neural construct, a brain-generated simulation. There is remarkable similarity between this account and ideas found in and developed by German neo-Kantians in the mid-nineteenth century. Some of the neo-Kantians eventually came to have doubts about the cogency and internal consistency of the representationalist framework they were operating within. In this paper, I will first argue that some of these concerns ought to be taken seriously by contemporary proponents of predictive coding. After having done so, I will turn to phenomenology. As we shall see, Husserl’s endorsement of transcendental idealism was partially motivated by his rejection of representationalism and phenomenalism and by his attempt to safeguard the objectivity of the world of experience. This confronts us with an intriguing question. Which position is best able to accommodate our natural inclination for realism: Contemporary neuro-representationalism or Husserl’s transcendental idealism?

References

  1. Allison, H. E. (1995). On naturalizing Kant’s transcendental psychology. Dialectica, 49(2–4), 335–356.Google Scholar
  2. Allison, H. E. (2015). From transcendental realism to transcendental idealism: The nature and significance of Kant’s ‘transcendental turn’. In S. Gardner & M. Grist (Eds.), The transcendental turn (pp. 20–34). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Anderson, M. L., & Chemero, T. (2013). The problem with brain GUTs: Conflation of different senses of ‘prediction’ threatens metaphysical disaster. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 204–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  5. Bruineberg, J., Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2016). The anticipating brain is not a scientist: The free-energy principle from an ecological-enactive perspective. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-016-1239-1.Google Scholar
  6. Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 181–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs. doi: 10.1111/nous.12140.Google Scholar
  8. Edgar, S. (2013). The limits of experience and explanation: F.A. Lange and Ernst Mach on things in themselves. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21(1), 100–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Fichte, J.G. (1988). Early philosophical writings. D. Breazeale (Trans.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Friston, K. (2010). The free–energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Frith, C. (2007). Making up the mind: How the brain creates our mental worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Gallagher, S., & Allen, M. (2016). Active inference, enactivism and the hermeneutics of social cognition. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-016-1269-8.Google Scholar
  13. Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 53–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hegel, G.W.F. (2010 [1830]). Encyclopedia of the philosophical sciences in basic outline. Part I: Science of logic. K. Brinkmann and D. O. Dahlstrom (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Heidegger, M. (1985 [1925]). History of the concept of time. T. Kisiel (Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Helmholtz, H.v. (1855). Das Sehen des Menschen. Leipzig: Leopold Voss.Google Scholar
  17. Helmholtz, H.v. (1995 [1853/1892]). Science and culture: Popular and philosophical lectures. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Hobson, J. A., & Friston, K. J. (2014). Consciousness, dreams, and inference: The Cartesian theatre revisited. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21(1–2), 6–32.Google Scholar
  19. Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hohwy, J. (2016). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs, 50(2), 259–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Hopp, W. (2011). Perception and knowledge: A phenomenological account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Husserl, E. (1960 [1929/1950]). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology. D. Cairns (Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  23. Husserl, E. (1982 [1913]). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. First book. General introduction to a pure phenomenology. F. Kersten (Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  24. Husserl, E. (2003). Transzendentaler Idealismus. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1921). Husserliana 36. R. Rollinger (Ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  25. Jacobi, F. H. (2000 [1787]). On transcendental idealism. In B. Sassen (Ed.), Kant’s early critics: The empiricist critique of the theoretical philosophy (pp. 169–175). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Kant, I. (1998 [1787]). Critique of pure reason. P. Guyer and A. W. Wood (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Kant, I. (2005 [1785-1789]). Notes and fragments. C. Bowman, P. Guyer, F. Rauscher (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Kock, L. D. (2014). Hermann von Helmholtz’s empirico-transcendentalism reconsidered: Construction and constitution in Helmholtz’s psychology of the object. Science in Context, 27(4), 709–744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Kock, L. D. (2016). Helmholtz’s Kant revisited. The all-pervasive nature of Helmholtz’s struggle with Kant’s Anschauung. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 56, 20–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lange, F. A. (1925 [1865]). The history of materialism and criticism of its present importance. E. C. Thomas (Trans.). London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  31. Mach, E. (1895 [1882]). The economical nature of physical inquiry. In Popular scientific lectures. Th. J. McCormack (Trans.). Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  32. Metzinger, T. (2009). The ego tunnel. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  33. Müller, J. (1842). Elements of physiology II. W. Baly (Trans.). London: Taylor and WaltonGoogle Scholar
  34. Putnam, H. (1987). The many faces of realism. LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court.Google Scholar
  35. Sartre, J.-P. (1970) [1939]. Intentionality: A fundamental idea of Husserl’s phenomenology. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 1(2), 4–5.Google Scholar
  36. Slaby, J., & Heilinger, J.-C. (2013). Lost in phenospace: Questioning the claims of popular neurophilosophy. Metodo, 1(2), 83–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Swanson, L. R. (2016). The predictive processing paradigm has roots in Kant. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 10(79), 1–13. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2016.00079.Google Scholar
  38. Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  39. Zahavi, D. (2003). Phenomenology and metaphysics. In D. Zahavi, S. Heinämaa, & H. Ruin (Eds.), Metaphysics, facticity, interpretation (pp. 3–22). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Zahavi, D. (2004). Phenomenology and the project of naturalization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(4), 331–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Zahavi, D. (2008). Internalism, externalism, and transcendental idealism. Synthese, 160(3), 355–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Zahavi, D. (2010). Husserl and the ‘absolute’. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, phenomenology, sciences: Essays in commemoration of Husserl (pp. 71–92). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  43. Zahavi, D. (2013). Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 72, 23–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Zahavi, D. (2017). Husserl’s legacy: Phenomenology, metaphysics, and transcendental idealism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Center for Subjectivity ResearchUniversity of CopenhagenCopenhagen SDenmark

Personalised recommendations