Advertisement

Health Care Analysis

, Volume 21, Issue 2, pp 130–145 | Cite as

Science, Practice and Mythology: A Definition and Examination of the Implications of Scientism in Medicine

  • Michael Loughlin
  • George Lewith
  • Torkel Falkenberg
Original Article

Abstract

Scientism is a philosophy which purports to define what the world ‘really is’. It adopts what the philosopher Thomas Nagel called ‘an epistemological criterion of reality’, defining what is real as that which can be discovered by certain quite specific methods of investigation. As a consequence all features of experience not revealed by those methods are deemed ‘subjective’ in a way that suggests they are either not real, or lie beyond the scope of meaningful rational inquiry. This devalues capacities that (we argue) are in fact essential components of good reasoning and virtuous practice. Ultimately, the implications of scientism for statements of value undermine value-judgements essential for science itself to have a sound basis. Scientism has implications, therefore, for ontology, epistemology and also for which claims we can assert as objective truths about the world. Adopting scientism as a world view will have consequences for reasoning and decision-making in clinical and other contexts. We analyse the implications of this approach and conclude that we need to reject scientism if we are to avoid stifling virtuous practice and to develop richer conceptions of human reasoning.

Keywords

Epistemology Ethics Judgement Objectivity Positivism Practice Rationality Science Scientism Value Virtue 

Notes

Acknowledgments

We are extremely grateful to John Gabbay, Paul Dieppe, Peter Fenwick and Harald Walach for their astute and thoughtful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  1. 1.
    Adams, D. (1992). The Hitch-Hiker’s guide to the galaxy: A trilogy in four parts. London: Pan Books.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Anscombe, E., & Geach, P. T. (1954). Descartes’ philosophical writings. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Ayer, A. J. (1987). Language, truth and logic. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books Ltd.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Baker, L. R. (2008). A metaphysics of ordinary things and why we need it. Philosophy, 83, 5–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Bluhm, R. (2010). Evidence-based medicine and philosophy of science. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 16(2), 363–364.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In J. Humber & R. Almeder (Eds.), What is disease? (pp. 3–34). Totowa: Humana Press.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Braude, H. (2011). Tacit clues and the science of clinical judgement. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 940–943.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Chalmers, A. F. (2003). What is this thing called science? (3rd ed.). Maidenhead: Open University Press.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Clark, S. R. L. (1988). Mackie and the moral order. Philosophical Quarterly, 39, 98–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Dans, A., Dans, L., & Silverstre, M. (2008). Painless evidence-based medicine. Chichester: Wiley.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Dennett, D. (2006). Breaking the spell. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Djulbegovic, B., Guyatt, G. H., & Ashcroft, R. E. (2009). Epistemologic inquiries in evidence-based medicine. Cancer Control, 16, 158–168.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Dupré, J. (2002). Humans and other animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Dupré, J. (2003). On human nature. Human Affairs, 13, 2.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Elton, M. (2003). Dennett: Reconciling science and our self-conception. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Evidence-Based Medicine Working Group. (1992). Evidence-based medicine: A new approach to teaching the practice of medicine. Journal of the American Medical Association, 268(17), 2420–2425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Fulford, K. W. M. (2001). What is (mental) disease? An open letter to Christopher Boorse. Journal of Medical Ethics, 27(2), 80–85.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Gabbay, J., & Le May, A. (2004). Evidence based guidelines or collectively constructed ‘mindlines’? Ethnographic study of knowledge management in primary care. BMJ, 329, 1013.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Gelhaus, P. (2011). Robot decisions: The importance of virtuous judgement in clinical decision-making. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 833–837.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Goldacre, B. (2006). Objectionable ‘objectives’. The Guardian. Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Goldacre, B. (2009). Bad science. London: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Goodman, K. (2003). Ethics and evidence-based medicine: Fallibility and responsibility in clinical science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Griffiths, P. E. (1998). What emotions really are. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Haack, S. (2003). Defending science within reason: Between scientism and cynicism. Amherst: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Hamilton, R. (2010). The concept of health: Beyond normativism and naturalism. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 16(2), 323–329.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for philosophers. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Hawking, S. (1990). A brief history of time. Chatham: Guild Publishing.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Henry, S. (2010). Polanyi’s tacit knowledge and the relevance of epistemology to clinical medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 16(2), 292–297.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Henry, S., Forman, J., & Fetters, M. (2011). How do you know what Aunt Martha looks like? A video elicitation exploring tacit clues in doctor-patient interactions. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 933–939.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. 32.
    Hume, D. (1989). A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Hursthouse, (2001). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. 34.
    Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis in European science and transcendental phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Hutchinson, (2008). Shame and philosophy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    Hutchinson, P., & Loughlin, M. (2009). Why teach Philosophy? Chapter 3 of Kenkman, A. (Ed.), Teaching philosophy (pp. 38–54). London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    IHSM. (1993). Future health care options, final report. London: The Institute of Health Services Management.Google Scholar
  38. 38.
    Kincaid, H., Dupré, J., & Wylie, A. (Eds.). (2007). Value-free science? Ideals and illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Kuhn, T. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Little, M., Lipworth, W., Gordon, J., Markham, P., & Kerridge, I. (2012) Another argument for values-based medicine. International Journal of Person Centered Medicine (in press).Google Scholar
  42. 42.
    Loughlin, M. (1994). Against Qualia: Our direct perception of physical reality. European Review of Philosophy, 1, 77–88.Google Scholar
  43. 43.
    Loughlin, A. J. (1998). Alienation and value-neutrality. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    Loughlin, M. (2002). Ethics, management and mythology. Oxon: Radcliffe Medical Press.Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    Loughlin, M. (2004). Management, science and reality. Philosophy of Management, 4(2), 35–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 46.
    Loughlin, M. (2008). Reason, reality and objectivity: Shared dogmas in the way both scientistic and postmodern commentators frame the EBM debate. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 14(5), 665–671.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. 47.
    Loughlin, M. (2009). The basis of medical knowledge: Judgement, objectivity and the history of ideas. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 15(6), 935–940.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. 48.
    Loughlin, M. (2010). Psychologism, overpsychologism and action. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 17(4), 305–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. 49.
    Loughlin, M., Upshur, R., Goldenberg, M., Bluhm, R., & Borgerson, K. (2010). Philosophy, ethics, medicine and health care: The urgent need for critical practice. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 16(2), 249–259.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. 50.
    Loughlin, M., Bluhm, R., Buetow, S., Goldenberg, M., Upshur, R., Borgerson, K., et al. (2011). Virtue, progress and practice. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 839–846.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. 51.
    MacIntyre, A. (1999). Dependent, rational animal: Why human beings need the virtues. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  52. 52.
    Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  53. 53.
    Macnaughton, J. (2011). Medical humanities’ challenge to medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 927–932.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. 54.
    Marcum, J. (2011). The role of prudent love in the practice of clinical medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 877–882.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. 55.
    Marx, K., & Theses on Feuerbach. Appendix to Engels, F. (1973). Ludwig Feuerbach and the end of classical German philosophy. Moscow: Progress Publishers.Google Scholar
  56. 56.
    Maxwell, N. (2004). Is science neurotic? London: Imperial College Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. 57.
    McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, value and reality, value and reality. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  58. 58.
    Miles, A. (2009). On a medicine of the whole person: Away from scientistic reductionism and towards the embrace of the complex in clinical practice. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 15(6), 941–949.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. 59.
    Miles, A., & Loughlin, M. (2011). Models in the balance: Evidence-based medicine versus evidence-informed individualized care. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(4), 531–536.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. 60.
    Miles, A., & Mezzich, J. (2011). The care of the patient and the soul of the clinic: Person-centred medicine as an emergent model of modern clinical practice. International Journal of Person Centred Medicine, 1(2), 217–222.Google Scholar
  61. 61.
    Miles, A., Loughlin, M., & Polychronis, A. (2008). Editorial introduction and commentary: ‘Evidence-based health care, clinical knowledge and the rise of personalised medicine’. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 14(5), 621–649.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. 62.
    Mill, J. S. (1991). On liberty. In Gray, J., & Smith, G. W. (Eds.). Routledge: London.Google Scholar
  63. 63.
    Mittra, I. (2009). Why is modern medicine stuck in a rut? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 52(4), 500–517.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. 64.
    Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  65. 65.
    Noe, A. (2009). Out of our heads. New York: Hill & Wang.Google Scholar
  66. 66.
    Nordenfelt, L. (2001). Health, science, and ordinary language. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  67. 67.
    Peterson, G. (2003). Demarcation and the scientistic fallacy. Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science, 38(4), 751–761.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. 68.
    Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47, 44–50.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. 69.
    Popper, K. (1989). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  70. 70.
    Putnam, H. (1992). Renewing philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  71. 71.
    Read, R. (2012). Wittgenstein among the sciences: Wittgensteinian investigations into the ‘scientific method’. Surrey: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  72. 72.
    Sackett, D. L., Rosenberg, W. M. C., Gray, J. A. M., Haynes, R. B., & Richardson, W. S. (1996). Evidence-based medicine: What it is and what it isn’t. British Medical Journal, 312, 71–72.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. 73.
    Simon, J. (2011). Progress in medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 847–851.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. 74.
    Sokal, A., & Bricmont, J. (1998). Intellectual impostures. London: Profile Books.Google Scholar
  75. 75.
    Sorabji, R. (1983). Time, creation and the continuum. Duckworth, London: Creation and the Continuum.Google Scholar
  76. 76.
    Sorell, T. (1994). Scientism: Philosophy and the infatuation with science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  77. 77.
    Thornton, T. (2011). Radical, liberal values-based practice. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 17(5), 911–988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. 78.
    Timmermans, S., & Berg, M. (2003). The gold standard: The challenge of evidence based medicine and standardization in health care. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
  79. 79.
    Tonelli, M. R. (1998). The philosophical limits of evidence-based medicine. Academic Medicine, 73(12), 1234–1240.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. 80.
    Tonelli, M. R. (2010). The challenge of evidence in clinical medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 16(2), 384–389.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. 81.
    Upshur, R. (2002). If not evidence, then what? Or does medicine really need a base? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 2, 113–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. 82.
    Vickers, A. J. (2010). Reducing systematic review to a cut and paste. Forsch Komplementmed, 17, 303–305.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. 83.
    Worrall, J. (2010). Evidence: philosophy of science meets medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 16(2), 356–362.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  • Michael Loughlin
    • 1
    • 2
  • George Lewith
    • 3
  • Torkel Falkenberg
    • 4
    • 5
  1. 1.Department of Interdisciplinary StudiesManchester Metropolitan University CheshireCrewe CheshireUK
  2. 2.University of BuckinghamBuckinghamUK
  3. 3.School of MedicineUniversity of SouthamptonSouthamptonUK
  4. 4.Department of Neurobiology, Care Sciences and Society, Division of Nursing, Unit for Studies of Integrative CareKarolinska InstitutetHuddingeSweden
  5. 5.The Integrative Care Science CentreJärnaSweden

Personalised recommendations