Foundations of Chemistry

, Volume 14, Issue 1, pp 55–68 | Cite as

Chemical substances and the limits of pluralism

Article

Abstract

In this paper I investigate the relationship between vernacular kind terms and specialist scientific vocabularies. Elsewhere I have developed a defence of realism about the chemical elements as natural kinds. This defence depends on identifying the epistemic interests and theoretical conception of the elements that have suffused chemistry since the mid-eighteenth century. Because of this dependence, it is a discipline-specific defence, and would seem to entail important concessions to pluralism about natural kinds. I argue that making this kind of concession does not imply that vernacular kind terms have independent application conditions. Nor does it preclude us saying that chemists, with their particular epistemic interests, have discovered the underlying nature of water, the stuff that is named and thought about in accordance with the practical interests of everyday life. There are limits to pluralism.

Keywords

Chemical substances Pluralism Limits 

References

  1. Abbott, B.: A note on the nature of ‘water’. Mind 106, 311–319 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Aston, F.W., et al.: Report of the International Committee on Chemical Elements. J. Am. Chem. Soc. 45, 866–874 (1923)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bird, A.: Discovering the essences of natural kinds. In: Beebee, H., Sabbarton-Leary, N. (eds.) The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds, pp. 125–136. Routledge, New York (2010)Google Scholar
  4. Bruzzaniti, G., Robotti, N.: The affirmation of the concept of isotopy and the birth of mass spectrography. Arch Internationales d’Histoires des Sci 39, 309–334 (1989)Google Scholar
  5. Chomsky, N.: Language and nature. Mind 104, 1–61 (1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Devitt, M., Sterelny, K.: Language and Reality, 2nd edn. Blackwell, Oxford (1999)Google Scholar
  7. Dupré, J.: Natural kinds and biological taxa. Philos Rev 90, 66–90 (1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dupré, J.: The Disorder of Things. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1993)Google Scholar
  9. Dupré, J.: Are whales fish? In: Medin, D.L., Atran, S. (eds.) Folkbiology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1999)Google Scholar
  10. Ellis, B.: The Philosophy of Nature: A Guide to the New Essentialism. Acumen, Chesham (2002)Google Scholar
  11. Ellis, B.: The Metaphysics of Scientific Realism. Acumen, Durham (2009)Google Scholar
  12. Ereshefsky, M.: Species. In: E. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010) URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/species/
  13. Feyerabend, P.: Explanation, reduction and empiricism. In: Feigl, H., Maxwell, G. (eds.) Scientific Explanation, Space and Time, pp. 28–97. University of Minneapolis Press, Minneapolis (1962)Google Scholar
  14. Franks, F. (ed.) Water: A Comprehensive Treatise, vol 1–7. Plenum, New York (1972–1982)Google Scholar
  15. Goodwin, W.: Mechanisms and chemical reaction. In: Hendry, R.F., Needham, P., Woody, A.I. (eds.) Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. Volume 6: Philosophy of Chemistry, pp. 310–327. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2011)Google Scholar
  16. Gordin, M.: A Well-Ordered Thing: Dmitrii Mendeleev and the Shadow of the Periodic Table. Basic Books, New York (2004)Google Scholar
  17. Hacking, I.: Putnam’s theory of natural kinds and their names is not the same as Kripke’s. Principia 11, 1–24 (2007)Google Scholar
  18. Hendry, R.F.: Review of Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change by Joseph LaPorte. Philos. Writ. 27, 71–75 (2004)Google Scholar
  19. Hendry, R.F.: Lavoisier and Mendeleev on the elements. Found. Chem. 7, 31–48 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hendry, R.F.: Elements, compounds and other chemical kinds. Philos. Sci. 73, 864–875 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Hendry, R.F.: Microstructuralism: problems and prospects. In: Ruthenberg, K., van Brakel, J. (eds.) Stuff: The Nature of Chemical Substances, pp. 107–120. Königshausen und von Neumann, Würzburg (2008)Google Scholar
  22. Hendry, R.F.: The elements and conceptual change. In: Beebee, Helen., Sabbarton-Leary, Nigel. (eds.) The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds, pp. 137–158. Routledge, London (2010a)Google Scholar
  23. Hendry, R.F.: The chemical bond: structure, energy and explanation. In: Dorato, Mauro., Rèdei, Miklós., Suárez, Mauricio. (eds.) EPSA Philosophical Issues in the Sciences: Launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 117–127. Springer, Berlin (2010b)Google Scholar
  24. Hendry, R.F.: Entropy and chemical substance. Philos. Sci. 77, 921–932 (2010c)Google Scholar
  25. Hendry, R.F., Needham, P.: Le Poidevin on the reduction of chemistry. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 58, 339–353 (2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Klein, U.: Origin of the concept of chemical compound. Sci. Context 7, 163–204 (1994)Google Scholar
  27. Klein, U., Lefèvre, W.: Materials in Eighteenth-Century Science: A Historical Ontology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (2007)Google Scholar
  28. Kragh, Helge.: Conceptual changes in chemistry: the notion of a chemical element, ca. 1900–1925. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 31B, 435–450 (2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Kuhn, T.S.: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1970)Google Scholar
  30. LaPorte, J.: Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)Google Scholar
  31. LaPorte, J.: Theoretical identity statements, their truth and their discovery. In: Beebee, H., Sabbarton-Leary, N. (eds.) The semantics and metaphysics of natural kinds, pp. 104–124. Routledge, London (2010)Google Scholar
  32. Le Poidevin, R.: Missing elements and missing premises: a combinatorial argument for the ontological reduction of chemistry. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 56, 117–134 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Malt, B.: Water is not H2O. Cogn. Psychol. 27, 41–70 (1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Needham, P.: An Aristotelian theory of chemical substance. Log. Anal. Hist. Philos. 12, 149–164 (2009)Google Scholar
  35. Putnam, H.: Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol 2. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Putnam, H.: Is water necessarily H2O? In: Conant, J. (ed.) Realism with a Human Face, pp. 54–79. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1990)Google Scholar
  37. Siegfried, R.: From Elements to Atoms: A History of Chemical Composition. American Philosophical Society, Philadelphia (2002)Google Scholar
  38. Thurlow, K.J.: IUPAC Nomenclature part 1, organic. In: Thurlow, K.J. (ed.) Chemical Nomenclature, pp. 103–126. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Tobin, E.: Crosscutting natural kinds and the hierarchy thesis. In: Beebee, H., Sabbarton-Leary N. (eds.) The semantics and metaphysics of natural kinds, pp. 179–191. Routledge, London (2010)Google Scholar
  40. van der Vet, P.: The debate between F.A. Paneth, G. von Hevesy and K. Fajans on the concept of chemical identity. Janus 92, 285–303 (1979)Google Scholar
  41. Weisberg, M.: Water is not H2O. In: Baird, D., McIntyre, L., Scerri, E. (eds.) Philosophy of Chemistry: Synthesis of a New Discipline, pp. 337–345. Springer, New York (2006)Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyDurham UniversityDurhamUK

Personalised recommendations