Advertisement

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice

, Volume 21, Issue 3, pp 629–647 | Cite as

Can We Use Social Policy to Enhance Compliance with Moral Obligations to Animals?

  • John BaslEmail author
  • Gina Schouten
Article

Abstract

Those who wish to abolish or restrict the use of non-human animals in so-called factory farming and/or experimentation often argue that these animal use practices are incommensurate with animals’ moral status. If sound, these arguments would establish that, as a matter of ethics or justice, we should voluntarily abstain from the immoral animal use practices in question. But these arguments can’t and shouldn’t be taken to establish a related conclusion: that the moral status of animals justifies political intervention to disallow or significantly diminish factory farming and animal experimentation. In this paper, we set out to do two things: First, we argue that while the arguments mentioned above may establish the moral impermissibility or injustice of the practices they condemn, they are not sufficient to justify political interventions or social policies to abolish or restrict such practices. It is one thing to argue that some moral imperative or imperative of justice exists, and quite another thing to call for the use of political power to induce compliance with that imperative. Our second task is to assess the prospects for developing an argument that is sufficient to justify political interventions to restrict or abolish the use of non-human animals in factory farming or experimentation. Beyond establishing the immorality or injustice of animal consumption or experimentation, one must show that the interventions in question constitute legitimate use of political power. Would prohibiting or discouraging animal use be legitimate? We attempt to answer this question within the context of fundamental liberal constraints on the legitimate use of coercive political power.

Keywords

Legitimacy Neutrality Animal justice Animal ethics Animal welfare Political philosophy 

Notes

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to the following people for feedback at various stages of this paper: Jeff Behrends, Brian Berkey, Eric Blumenson, Michael Bukoski, Candice Delmas, Mylan Engel Jr., David Faraci, Bo Kim Kopek, Matt Kopec, Katie McShane, Stephen Nathanson, Ronald Sandler, Eric Stencil, Daniel Wodak. We also received exceptional feedback after presenting these materials at the Rocky Mountain Ethics (RoME) Congress in 2015. We are especially grateful for Katie McShane’s comments on this work. We apologize for not being able to list all the attendees that offered feedback. Finally, we are thankful to anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful, helpful comments that much improved this paper.

References

  1. Abbey R (2007) Rawlsian resources for animal ethics. Ethics Environ 12(1):1–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Abbey R (2016) Putting cruelty first: exploring Judith Shklar’s liberalism of fear for animal ethics. Politics and Animals 2:25–36Google Scholar
  3. Abbey R (2017) Closer kinships: Rortyan resources for animal rights. Contemporary Political Theory 16:1–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Ackerman B (1980) Social justice in the liberal state. Yale University Press, New HavenGoogle Scholar
  5. Ackerman B (1994) Political liberalisms. J Philos 91(7):364–386CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Adams B, Larson J (2015) Legislative history of the animal welfare act: National Agricultural Library. https://www.nal.usda.gov/awic/legislative-history-animal-welfare-act-introduction. Accessed 13 Mar 2018
  7. Barry BM (1995) Justice as impartiality. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  8. Brighouse H (1995) Neutrality, publicity, and state funding of the arts. Philos Public Aff 24(1):35–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cochrrane A, Garner R, O'Sullivan S (2016) Animal ethics and the political. Crit Rev Int Soc Pol Phil 21:261–277Google Scholar
  10. Coeckelbergh M (2009) Distributive justice and co-operation in a world of humans and non-humans: a contractarian argument for drawing non-humans into the sphere of justice. Res Publica 15(1):67–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Cohen GA (1997) Where the action is: on the site of distributive justice. Philos Public Aff 26:3–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cohen J (2001) Taking people as they are? Philos Public Aff 30(4):363–386CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. DeGrazia D (2014) On the moral status of infants and the cognitively disabled: a reply to Jaworska and Tannenbaum. Ethics 124:543–556CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Donaldson S, Kymlicka W (2011) Zoopolis: a political theory of animal rights. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  15. Donaldson S, Kymlicka W (2012) Do we need a political theory of animal rights? In: Minding animals international conference. Utrecht, NetherlandsGoogle Scholar
  16. Engel M Jr (2012) The commonsense case against animal experimentation. In: Garret J (ed) The ethics of animal research: exploring the controversy, 1st edn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp 215–236CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Estlund D (1998) Debate: Liberalism, equality, and fraternity in Cohen’s critique of Rawls. J Polit Philos 6:99–112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Flanders C (2013) Public reason and animal rights. In: Wissenburg M, Schlosberg D (eds) Political animals and animal politics. Palgrave Macmillan, London, pp 44–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Francione GL (2009) Animals as persons: essays on the abolition of animal exploitation. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  20. Gallup. 2015. “In U.S., More Say Animals Should Have Same Rights as People.” Gallup.com. http://www.gallup.com/poll/183275/say-animals-rights-people.aspx
  21. Garner R (2003) Animals, politics and justice: Rawlsian liberalism and the plight of non-humans. Environmental Politics 12:3–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Garner R (2012) Rawls, animals and justice: new literature, same response. Res Publica 18:159–172CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Garner R (2013) A theory of justice for animals: animal rights in a nonideal world. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  24. Gruen L (2011) Ethics and animals: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  25. Horrigan L, Lawrence RS, Walker P (2002) How sustainable agriculture can address the environmental and human health harms of industrial agriculture. Environ Health Perspect 110:445–456CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Larmore CE (1987) Patterns of moral complexity. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  27. Larmore CE (1996) The morals of modernity. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  28. Milligan T (2015) The political turn in animal rights. Politics and Animals 1:6–15Google Scholar
  29. Moon JD (2012) Constructing community: moral pluralism and tragic conflicts. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJGoogle Scholar
  30. Murphy LB (1998) Institutions and the demands of justice. Philos Public Aff 27:251–291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Neufeld B (2009) Coercion, the basic structure, and the family. J Soc Philos 40:37–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Norcross A (2004) Puppies, pigs, and people: eating meat and marginal cases. Philos Perspect 18:229–245CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. O’Sullivan S (2007) Advocating for animals equally from within a liberal paradigm. Environmental Politics 16:1–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Pippin JJ (2005) The failure of animal tests of COX-2 inhibitors. http://www.physiciansforresponsiblemedicine.org/pdfs/research/testing/exp/COX2Report.pdf
  35. Pogge TW (2000) On the site of distributive justice: reflections on Cohen and Murphy. Philos Public Aff 29:137–169Google Scholar
  36. Quong J (2011) Liberalism without perfection. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  37. Rawls J(1999) A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  38. Rawls J (2005) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  39. Regan T (1983) The case for animal rights. University of California Press, BerkeleyGoogle Scholar
  40. Rowlands M (2002) Animals like us. Verso Press, LondonGoogle Scholar
  41. Rowlands M (2009) Animal rights: moral theory and practice. Palgrave Macmillan, BasingstokeGoogle Scholar
  42. Scheffler S (2006) Is the basic structure basic? In: Sypnowich C (ed) The egalitarian conscience: essays in honour of G. A. Cohen. Oxford University Press, pp 102–129Google Scholar
  43. Schouten G (2013) Restricting justice: political interventions in the home and in the market. Philos Public Aff 41:357–388CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Singer P (2009) Animal liberation: the definitive classic of the animal movement. Harper Collins, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  45. Smith KK (2012) Governing animals: animal welfare and the liberal state. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  46. Steinfeld H, Gerber P, Wassenaar TD, et al (2006) Livestock’s long shadow: environmental issues and options. United Nations Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO) http://www.fao.org/docrep/010/a0701e/a0701e00.HTM
  47. Streiffer R, Basl J (2011) Ethical issues in the application of biotechnology to animals in agriculture. In: Beauchamp TL, Frey RG (eds) The oxford handbook of animal ethics. OUP USA, pp 826–854Google Scholar
  48. Tan K-C (2004) Justice and personal pursuits. J Philos 101:331–362CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Tremain S (2013) Introducing feminist philosophy of disability. In: Disability studies quarterlyGoogle Scholar
  50. VanDeVeer D (1979) Of beasts, persons, and the original position. The Monist 62:368–377CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Williams A (1998) Incentives, inequality, and publicity. Philos Public Aff 27:225–247CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Wolff J (1998) Fairness, respect, and the egalitarian ethos. Philos Public Aff 27:97–122CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Northeastern UniversityBostonUSA
  2. 2.Harvard UniversityCambridgeUSA

Personalised recommendations