Ethical Theory and Moral Practice

, Volume 17, Issue 4, pp 761–774 | Cite as

Accounting for the Data: Intuitions in Moral Theory Selection

Article

Abstract

Reflective equilibrium is often credited with extending the idea of accounting for the data from its familiar home in the sciences to the realm of moral philosophy. But careful consideration of the main concepts of this idea—the data to be accounted for and the kind of accounting it is appropriate to expect of a moral theory—leads to a revised understanding of the “accounting for the data” perspective as it applies to the discipline of moral theory selection. This revised understanding is in tension with reflective equilibrium and actually provides more support for the alternative method of moral theory selection that has been termed ‘practical equilibrium’.

Keywords

Reflective equilibrium Practical equilibrium Intuitions Data 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Dale Miller and two anonymous reviewers for this journal for their comments on previous versions of this article. Special thanks are due to one of the reviewers, who provided several sets of extensive comments. That reviewer is the reviewer mentioned in footnotes 2–4 of this article, but his or her comments were so detailed and constructive as to lead, in total, to beneficial revisions throughout this article.

References

  1. Daniels N (1979) Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics. J Philos 76:256–282CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Daniels N (1980) On some methods of ethics and linguistics. Philos Stud 37:21–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Eggleston B (2010) Practical equilibrium: a way of deciding what to think about morality. Mind 119:549–584CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Frey RG (1977) Act-utilitarianism: Sidgwick or Bentham and Smart? Mind 86:95–100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Frey RG (2000) Act-utilitarianism. In: LaFollette H (ed) The Blackwell guide to ethical theory. Blackwell, Malden, pp 165–182Google Scholar
  6. Harman G (1977) The nature of morality: an introduction to ethics. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  7. Hogarth RM (2001) Educating intuition. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  8. Hooker B (2000) Ideal code, real world: a rule-consequentialist theory of morality. Clarendon, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  9. Musschenga AW (2009) Moral intuitions, moral expertise and moral reasoning. J Philos Educ 43:597–613CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Musschenga AW (2010) The epistemic value of intuitive moral judgements. Philos Explor 13:113–128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Rawls J (1951) Outline of a decision procedure for ethics. Philos Rev 60:177–197CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  13. Rawls J (1975) The independence of moral theory. Proc Addresses Am Philos Assoc 48:5–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Rescher N (1979) Reply to Hare. In: Sosa E (ed) The philosophy of Nicholas Rescher: discussion and replies. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 153–155CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ross WD (1930) The right and the good. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  16. Shaw WH (1980) Intuition and moral philosophy. Am Philos Q 17:127–134Google Scholar
  17. Shaw WH (1999) Contemporary ethics: taking account of utilitarianism. Blackwell, MaldenGoogle Scholar
  18. Singer P (1974) Sidgwick and reflective equilibrium. Monist 58:490–517CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Singer P (1998) Foreword. In: Brandt RB (ed) A theory of the good and the right. Prometheus, Amherst, pp v–ixGoogle Scholar
  20. Sinnott-Armstrong W (2006) Moral intuitionism meets empirical psychology. In: Horgan T, Timmons M (eds) Metaethics after Moore. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 339–365Google Scholar
  21. Symons J (2008) Intuition and philosophical methodology. Axiomathes 18:67–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of KansasLawrenceUSA

Personalised recommendations