Advertisement

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice

, Volume 16, Issue 5, pp 983–997 | Cite as

What Carroll’s Tortoise Actually Proves

  • Jan Willem Wieland
Article

Abstract

Rationality requires us to have certain propositional attitudes (beliefs, intentions, etc.) given certain other attitudes that we have. Carroll’s Tortoise repeatedly shows up in this discussion. Following up on Brunero (Ethical Theory Moral Pract 8:557–569, 2005), I ask what Carroll-style considerations actually prove. This paper rejects two existing suggestions, and defends a third.

Keywords

Rationality Attitude Obligation Regress Carroll Tortoise 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to: Erik Weber and the referees of the journal for extensive feedback. The author is PhD fellow of the Research Foundation Flanders.

References

  1. Blackburn S (1995) Practical tortoise raising. Mind 104:695–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Broome J (2002) Practical reasoning. In: Bermùdez J, Millar A (eds) Reason and nature. Essays in the theory of rationality. OUP, Oxford, pp 85–111Google Scholar
  3. Broome J (2005) Does rationality give us reasons? Philoso Issues 15:321–337CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brunero J (2005) Instrumental rationality and Carroll’s tortoise. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 8:557–569CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Caroll L (1895) What the tortoise said to Achilles. Mind 4:278–280 (C. L. Dodgson)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dreier J (1997) Humean doubts about the practical justification of morality. In: Cullity G et al (eds) Ethics and practical reason. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 81–100Google Scholar
  7. Dreier J (2001) Humean doubts about categorical imperatives. In: Millgram E (ed) Varieties of practical reasoning. MIT, Cambridge, MA, pp 27–47Google Scholar
  8. Engel P (2005) Logical reasons. Philos Explor 8:21–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Jollimore T (2005) Why is instrumental rationality rational? Can J Philos 35:289–307Google Scholar
  10. Kolodny N (2005) Why be rational? Mind 114:509–563CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Lazar A (1999) Akrasia and the principle of continence or what the tortoise would say to Achilles. In: Hahn LE (ed) The philosophy of Donald Davidson. Open Court, Chicago, Ill, pp 381–401Google Scholar
  12. Railton P (1997) On the hypothetical and non-hypothetical in reasoning about belief and action. In: Cullity G et al (eds) Ethics and practical reason. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 53–79Google Scholar
  13. Ryle G (1950) If’, ‘so’, and ‘because. In: Black M (ed) Philosophical analysis. CUP, Ithaca, pp 302–318Google Scholar
  14. Schueler GF (1995) Why ‘oughts’ are not facts (or what the tortoise and Achilles taught Mrs. Ganderhoot and me about practical reason). Mind 104:713–723CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Schwartz J (2010) Do hypothetical imperatives require categorical imperatives? Eur J Philos 18:84–107CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Setiya K (2009) Intention. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. <http://plato.stanford.edu/>
  17. Smiley T (1995) A tale of two tortoises. Mind 104:725–736CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Streumer B (2010) Practical reasoning. In: O’Connor T, Sandis C (eds) A companion to the philosophy of action. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 244–251CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Stroud B (1979) Inference, belief, and understanding. Mind 88:179–196CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Thomson JF (1960) What Achilles should have said to the tortoise. Ratio 3:95–105Google Scholar
  21. Way J (2010) The normativity of rationality. Philos Compass 5:1057–1068CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Wedgwood R (2005) Railton on normativity. Philos Stud 126:463–479CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Wieland JW (2012) And so on. Two theories of regress arguments in philosophy. Ghent University, PhD dissertationGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy and Moral ScienceGhent UniversityGhentBelgium

Personalised recommendations