Advertisement

Ethical Theories and the Transparency Condition

  • Johan BrännmarkEmail author
Article

Abstract

Following John Rawls, writers like Bernard Williams and Christine Korsgaard have suggested that a transparency condition should be put on ethical theories. The exact nature of such a condition and its implications is however not anything on which there is any consensus. It is argued here that the ultimate rationale of transparency conditions is epistemic rather than substantively moral, but also that it clearly connects to substantive concerns about moral psychology. Finally, it is argued that once a satisfactory form of the transparency condition is formulated, then, at least among the main contenders within ethical theory, it speaks in favor of a broadly Aristotelian approach to ethical theorizing.

Keywords

Ethics Methodology Moral psychology Practicality Transparency 

References

  1. Aristotle (1999) Nicomachean ethics. Irwin TH (trans) Hackett, IndianapolisGoogle Scholar
  2. Baron M (1995) Kantian ethics almost without apology. Cornell University Press, IthacaGoogle Scholar
  3. Bradley FH (1927) Ethical studies, 2nd edn. Clarendon, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  4. Chappell T (2008) Moral perception. Philosophy 83:421–437 doi: 10.1017/S0031819108000818 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dancy J (1993) Moral reasons. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  6. Hare RM (1981) Moral thinking. Clarendon, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Herman B (1993) The practice of moral judgment. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  8. Herman B (1996) Making room for character. In: Engstrom S, Whiting J (eds) Aristotle, Kant, and the stoics: rethinking happiness and duty. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  9. Hursthouse R (1999) On virtue ethics. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  10. Irwin TH (2000) Ethics as an inexact science: Aristotle’s ambitions for moral theory. In: Hooker B, Little M (eds) Moral particularism. Clarendon, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  11. Jackson F (1991) Decision-theoretic consequentialism and the nearest and dearest objection. Ethics 101:461–482 doi: 10.1086/293312 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kihlbom U (2000) Guidance and justification in particularistic ethics. Bioethics 14:287–309 doi: 10.1111/1467-8519.00199 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Korsgaard C (1996) The sources of normativity. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  14. McDowell J (1998) Mind, value, and reality. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  15. Nussbaum M (2001) Women and human development. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  16. O’Neill O (1989) Constructions of reason. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  17. Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Clarendon, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  18. Pettit P, Brennan G (1986) Restrictive consequentialism. Australas J Philos 64:438–455 doi: 10.1080/00048408612342631 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Railton P (1984) Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality. Philos Public Aff 13:134–171Google Scholar
  20. Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  21. Rawls J (1993) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  22. Slote M (2001) Morals from motives. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Väyrynen P (2006) Ethical theories and moral guidance. Utilitas 18:291–309 doi: 10.1017/S0953820806002056 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Williams B (1981) Moral luck. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  25. Williams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Fontana, LondonGoogle Scholar
  26. Williams B (1995) Acting as the virtuous person acts. In: Heinaman R (ed) Aristotle and moral realism. UCL, LondonGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyLund UniversityLundSweden

Personalised recommendations