Advertisement

Splintering the gamer’s dilemma: moral intuitions, motivational assumptions, and action prototypes

  • Jens Kjeldgaard-ChristiansenEmail author
Original Paper

Abstract

The gamer’s dilemma (Luck in Ethics Inf Technol 11(1):31–36, 2009) asks whether any ethical features distinguish virtual pedophilia, which is generally considered impermissible, from virtual murder, which is generally considered permissible. If not, this equivalence seems to force one of two conclusions: either both virtual pedophilia and virtual murder are permissible, or both virtual pedophilia and virtual murder are impermissible. In this article, I attempt, first, to explain the psychological basis of the dilemma. I argue that the two different action types picked out by “virtual pedophilia” and “virtual murder” set very different expectations for their token instantiations that systematically bias judgments of permissibility. In particular, the proscription of virtual pedophilia rests on intuitions about immoral desire, sexual violations, and a schematization of a powerful adult offending against an innocent child. I go on to argue that these differences between virtual pedophilia and virtual murder may be ethically relevant. Precisely because virtual pedophilia is normally aversive in a way that virtual murder is not, we plausibly expect virtual pedophilia to invite abnormal and immorally desirous forms of engagement.

Keywords

Gamer’s dilemma Virtual ethics Media ethics Virtual pedophilia Virtual violence 

Notes

References

  1. Ali, R. (2015). A new solution to the gamer’s dilemma. Ethics and Information Technology,17(4), 267–274.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-015-9381-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bartel, C. (2012). Resolving the gamer’s dilemma. Ethics and Information Technology,14(1), 11–16.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-011-9280-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Batson, C. D. (2011). Altruism in humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Brosnan, K. (2011). Do the evolutionary origins of our moral beliefs undermine moral knowledge? Biology and Philosophy,26(1), 51–64.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9235-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Buss, D. M. (2006). The murderer next door: Why the mind is designed to kill. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  6. Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2015). Harmful situations, impure people: An attribution asymmetry across moral domains. Cognition,136, 30–37.  https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2014.11.034.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  8. Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dworkin, G. (1995). Unprincipled ethics. Midwest Studies in Philosophy,20(1), 224–239.  https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1995.tb00314.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gaut, B. (1998). The ethical criticism of art. In J. Levinson (Ed.), Aesthetics and ethics: Essays at the intersection (pp. 182–203). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Giner-Sorolla, R., & Chapman, H. A. (2017). Beyond purity: Moral disgust toward bad character. Psychological Science,28(1), 80–91.  https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797616673193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Giner-Sorolla, R., Kupfer, T., & Sabo, J. (2018). What makes moral disgust special? An integrative functional review. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology,57, 223–289.  https://doi.org/10.1016/bs.aesp.2017.10.001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Goerger, M. (2017). Value, violence, and the ethics of gaming. Ethics and Information Technology,19(2), 95–105.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-017-9417-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S. P., et al. (2013). Chapter two: Moral foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology,47, 55–130.  https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-407236-7.00002-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,101(2), 366–385.  https://doi.org/10.1037/a0021847.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Gray, K., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2012). The moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry,23(2), 206–215.  https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2012.686247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Grizzard, M., Fitzgerald, K., Francemone, C. J., Ahn, C., Huang, J., Walton, J., … Eden, A. (2019). Validating the extended character morality questionnaire. Media Psychology, 1–24.  https://doi.org/10.1080/15213269.2019.1572523.
  18. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review,108(4), 814.  https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295x.108.4.814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science,316(5827), 998–1002.  https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1137651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
  21. Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: How innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues. Daedalus,133(4), 55–66.  https://doi.org/10.1162/0011526042365555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hazlett, A. (2009). How to defend response moralism. The British Journal of Aesthetics,49(3), 241–255.  https://doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayp020.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hutcherson, C. A., & Gross, J. J. (2011). The moral emotions: A social-functionalist account of anger, disgust, and contempt. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,100(4), 719–737.  https://doi.org/10.1037/a0022408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Joeckel, S., Bowman, N. D., & Dogruel, L. (2012). Gut or game? The influence of moral intuitions on decisions in video games. Media Psychology,15(4), 460–485.  https://doi.org/10.1080/15213269.2012.727218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kass, L. (1997). The wisdom of repugnance. The New Republic,216(22), 17–26.Google Scholar
  26. Krcmar, M., & Cingel, D. P. (2016). Moral foundations theory and moral reasoning in video game play: Using real-life morality in a game context. Journal of Broadcasting & Electronic Media,60(1), 87–103.  https://doi.org/10.1080/08838151.2015.1127246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Luck, M. (2009). The gamer’s dilemma: An analysis of the arguments for the moral distinction between virtual murder and virtual paedophilia. Ethics and Information Technology,11(1), 31–36.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-008-9168-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Luck, M. (2018). Has Ali dissolved the gamer’s dilemma? Ethics and Information Technology,20(3), 157–162.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-018-9455-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Luck, M., & Ellerby, N. (2013). Has Bartel resolved the gamer’s dilemma? Ethics and Information Technology,15(3), 229–233.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-013-9322-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Matthew, G., Ron, T., Lewis, R. J., Wang, L., & Prabhu, S. (2014). Being bad in a video game can make us morally sensitive. Cyberpsychology, Behavior, and Social Networking,17(8), 499–504.  https://doi.org/10.1089/cyber.2013.0658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs,41(4), 663–685.  https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Ostritsch, S. (2017). The amoralist challenge to gaming and the gamer’s moral obligation. Ethics and Information Technology,19(2), 117–128.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-017-9420-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Parkin, S. (2012). Who spilled hot coffee? The man who uncovered gaming’s greatest sex scandal. Eurogamer. Retrieved from https://www.eurogamer.net/articles/2012-11-30-who-spilled-hot-coffee.
  34. Patridge, S. (2011). The incorrigible social meaning of video game imagery. Ethics and Information Technology,13(4), 303–312.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-010-9250-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Patridge, S. L. (2013). Pornography, ethics, and video games. Ethics and Information Technology,15(1), 25–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Prinz, J. (2007). The emotional construction of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Ross, C. C. (2012). Overexposed and under-prepared: The effects of early exposure to sexual content. Psychology Today. Retrieved from https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/real-healing/201208/overexposed-and-under-prepared-the-effects-early-exposure-sexual-content.
  38. Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011). Moral anger, but not moral disgust, responds to intentionality. Emotion,11(2), 233–240.  https://doi.org/10.1037/a0022598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Sabo, J. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2017). Imagining wrong: Fictitious contexts mitigate condemnation of harm more than impurity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,146(1), 134–153.  https://doi.org/10.1037/xge0000251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2018). The theory of dyadic morality: Reinventing moral judgment by redefining harm. Personality and Social Psychology Review,22(1), 32–70.  https://doi.org/10.1177/1088868317698288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Schulzke, M. (2010). Defending the morality of violent video games. Ethics and Information Technology,12(2), 127–138.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-010-9222-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Shafer-Landau, R. (2012). Evolutionary debunking, moral realism and moral knowledge. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy,7(1), 1–37.  https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v7i1.68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M., & Miller, J. G. (1987). Culture and moral development. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of morality in young children (pp. 1–83). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  44. Tamborini, R. (2011). Moral intuition and media entertainment. Journal of Media Psychology,23(1), 39–45.  https://doi.org/10.1027/1864-1105/a000031.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Tamborini, R., Weber, R., Bowman, N. D., Eden, A., & Skalski, P. (2013). “Violence is a many-splintered thing”: The importance of realism, justification, and graphicness in understanding perceptions of and preferences for violent films and video games. Projections,7(1), 100–118.  https://doi.org/10.3167/proj.2013.070108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Vaage, M. B. (2015a). The antihero in American television. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Vaage, M. B. (2015b). On the repulsive rapist and the difference between morality in fiction and real life. In L. Zunshine (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of cognitive literary studies (pp. 421–439). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Wisneski, D. C., & Skitka, L. J. (2017). Moralization through moral shock: Exploring emotional antecedents to moral conviction. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,43(2), 139–150.  https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167216676479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Young, G. (2013). Enacting taboos as a means to an end; but what end? On the morality of motivations for child murder and paedophilia within gamespace. Ethics and Information Technology,15(1), 13–23.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-012-9306-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Young, G. (2016). Resolving the gamer’s dilemma: Examining the moral and psychological differences between virtual murder and virtual pedophilia. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Zacks, J. M., Speer, N. K., Swallow, K. M., Braver, T. S., & Reynolds, J. R. (2007). Event perception: A mind-brain perspective. Psychological Bulletin,133(2), 273–293.  https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.133.2.273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Zacks, J. M., Tversky, B., & Iyer, G. (2001). Perceiving, remembering, and communicating structure in events. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,130(1), 29–58.  https://doi.org/10.1037//0096-3445.130.1.29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of EnglishAarhus UniversityAarhus CDenmark

Personalised recommendations