Advertisement

Erkenntnis

pp 1–34 | Cite as

Analyzing Theories in the Frame Model

  • Stephan Kornmesser
  • Gerhard Schurz
Original Research
  • 59 Downloads

Abstract

The frame model was developed in cognitive psychology and imported into the philosophy of science in order to provide representations of scientific concepts and conceptual taxonomies. The aim of this article is to show that beside the representation of scientific concepts the frame model is an efficient instrument to represent and analyze scientific theories. That is, we aim to establish the frame model as a representation tool for the structure of theories within the philosophy of science. For this, we will develop the notion of a theory frame and distinguish between theory frames for qualitative theories in which scientific measurement is based on nominal scales and theory frames for quantitative theories in which measurement is based on ratio scales. In three case studies, we will apply frames to a psychological, a linguistic, and a physical theory, thereby showing that the frame model is a powerful and intuitively accessible instrument to analyze the laws of scientific theories, the determination of theoretical concepts, the explanatory role of theoretical concepts, the abductive introduction of a new theoretical concept, the distinction between the core and the periphery of a theory, the diachronic development of a theory, and the distinction between qualitative and quantitative scientific concepts. Finally, we will provide a comparison to the structuralist view of theories, one of the most elaborated and applied models of theory representation.

Keywords

Frame Theory Theoretical concept Qualitative and quantitative measurement Structuralist view of theories 

References

  1. Andersen, H., Barker, P., & Chen, X. (1996). Kuhn’s mature philosophy of science and cognitive psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 9, 347–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Andersen, H., Barker, P., & Chen, X. (2006). The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge: University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Andersen, H., & Nersessian, N. J. (2000). Nomic concepts, frames, and conceptual change. Philosophy of Science, 67(Proceedings), S224–S241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Balzer, W., Moulines, C. U., & Sneed, J. D. (1987). An architectonic for science. The structuralist program. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Balzer, W., & Sneed, J. D. (1977). Generalized net structures of empirical theories, part I. Studia Logica, 36, 195–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Barker, P., Chen, X., & Andersen, H. (2003). Kuhn on concepts and categorization. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Thomas Kuhn (pp. 212–245). Cambridge: University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Barsalou, L. W. (1992). Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In A. Lehrer & E. F. Kittay (Eds.), Frames, fields, and contrasts (pp. 21–74). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  8. Barsalou, L. W., & Hale, C. R. (1993). Components of conceptual representation: From feature lists to recursive frames. In I. Van Mechelen, J. Hampton, R. S. Michalski, & P. Theuns (Eds.), Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive data analysis (pp. 97–144). London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  9. Busse, D. (2012). Frame-Semantik. Ein Kompendium. Berlin/Boston: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Carnap, R. (1936). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Chen, X. (2003). Object and event concepts. A cognitive mechanism of incommensurability. Philosophy of Science, 70, 962–974.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Chen, X., Andersen, H., & Barker, P. (1998). Kuhn’s theory of scientific revolutions and cognitive psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 11, 5–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Chen, X., & Barker, P. (2000). Continuity through revolutions: a frame-based account of conceptual change during scientific revolutions. Philosophy of Science, 67, 208–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.Google Scholar
  15. Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of language. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
  16. Chomsky, N., & Lasnik, H. (1977). Filters and control. Linguistic Inquiry, 8, 425–504.Google Scholar
  17. Gamerschlag, T., Gerland, D., Osswald, R., & Petersen, W. (Eds.). (2014). Concept types and frames. Application in language, cognition, and science. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  18. Gilligan, G. M. (1987). A cross-linguistic approach to the pro-drop parameter. University of California Ph. D. Dissertation.Google Scholar
  19. Halliday, D., Resnick, R., & Walker, J. (2008). Fundamentals of physics (8th ed.). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
  20. Hand, D. J. (2004). Measurement theory and practice. London: Arnold.Google Scholar
  21. Hempel, C. G. (1973). The meaning of theoretical terms: A critique of the standard empiricist construal. In P. Suppes, L. Henkin, A. Joja, & G. C. Moisil (Eds.), Logic, methodology and the philosophy of science (pp. 367–378). London & Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing.Google Scholar
  22. Kayne, R. S. (1980). Extensions of binding and case-marking. Linguistic Inquiry, 11, 75–96.Google Scholar
  23. Kornmesser, S. (2012). Model-based research programs. Conceptus, 41, 135–187.Google Scholar
  24. Kornmesser, S. (2016). A frame-based approach for theoretical concepts. Synthese, 193, 145–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kornmesser, S. (2017). A frame-based approach for operationalized concepts. In M. Michela Massimi, J.-W. Romeijn, & G. Schurz (Eds.), Recent developments in the philosophy of science—EPSA15 Düsseldorf. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  26. Kornmesser, S. (2018). Frames and concepts in the philosophy of science. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8, 225–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Kuhn, T. S. (2010). Afterwords. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes (pp. 311–341). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  28. Moulines, C. U. (2000). Is there genuinely scientific progress? In A. Jonkisz & L. Koj (Eds.), On comparing and evaluating scientific theories (pp. 173–197). Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  29. Moulines, C. U. (2002). Introduction: Structuralism as a program for modelling theoretical science. Synthese, 130, 1–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Perlmutter, D. M. (1971). Deep and surface structure constraints in syntax. New York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston Inc.Google Scholar
  31. Petersen, W. (2007). Representation of concepts as frames. In J. Skilters, F. Toccafondi, & G. Stemberg (Eds.), Complex cognition and qualitative science. The Baltic international yearbook of cognition, logic and communication (Vol. 2, pp. 151–170). Riga: University of Latvia.Google Scholar
  32. Rizzi, L. (1982). Issues in Italian syntax. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Rosch, E. (1978). Principles of categorization. In E. Rosch & B. B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization (pp. 27–48). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  34. Rosch, E., Mervis, C. B., Gray, W. D., Johnson, D. M., & Boyes-Bream, P. (1976). Basic objects in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8, 382–439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Schurz, G. (2008). Patterns of abduction. Synthese, 164, 201–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Schurz, G. (2013). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  37. Schurz, G. (2016). Common cause abduction: The formation of theoretical concepts and models in science. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 24(4), 494–509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Stegmüller, W. (1986). Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie. Band II. Theorie und Erfahrung. Dritter Teilband. Die Entwicklung des neuen Strukturalismus seit 1973. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  39. Stevens, S. S. (1946). On the theory of scales of measurement. Science, 103, 677–680.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. van der Auwera, J. (1984). Subject vs. non-subject asymmetries in the relativization of embedded NP’s. In W. de Geest & Y. Putseys (Eds.), Sentential complementation. Proceedings of the international conference held at UFSAL, Brussels, June 1983 (pp. 257–269). Dordrecht: Foris Publications.Google Scholar
  41. Votsis, I., & Schurz, G. (2012). A frame-theoretic analysis of two rival conceptions of heat. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 43(1), 105–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Votsis, I., & Schurz, G. (2014). Reconstructing scientific theory change by means of frames. In T. Gamerschlag, D. Gerland, R. Osswald, & W. Petersen (Eds.), Concept types and frames. Application in language, cognition, and science (pp. 93–110). New York: Springer.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute of PhilosophyCarl von Ossietzky Universität OldenburgOldenburgGermany
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyHeinrich Heine University DuesseldorfDuesseldorfGermany

Personalised recommendations