Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 80, Issue 3, pp 657–673 | Cite as

No Match Point for the Permissibility Account

  • Anna-Maria Asunta Eder
Original Article

Abstract

In the literature, one finds two accounts of the normative status of rational belief: the ought account and the permissibility account. Both accounts have their advantages and shortcomings, making it difficult to favour one over the other. Imagine that there were two principles of rational belief or rational degrees of belief commonly considered plausible, but which, however, yielded a paradox together with one account, but not with the other. One of the accounts therefore requires us to give up one of the plausible principles; whereas the other allows us to save them both. The fact that it allows us to save both of the plausible principles might well be considered a strong reason in favour of the relevant account. The permissibility-account-based resolution of the lottery paradox suggests that the permissibility account is a candidate for being supported in this way, since the account seems to save two plausible principles of rational belief and rational degrees of belief. I argue that even if the permissibility account were supported in this way the support would be defeated, since one cannot provide an analogous resolution of the preface paradox. The principles remain unsaved by the permissibility account.

Keywords

Strong Reason Rational Belief Epistemic Justification Ticket Lottery Total Evidence 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Peter Brössel, Thomas Kroedel, Hannes Leitgeb, Wolfgang Spohn, Raphael van Riel, and Ben Young for insightful suggestions and comments on previous versions of this paper. I am also grateful to three anonymous referees for providing very helpful remarks. My research was funded by the Volkswagenstiftung (Dilthey Program) through the research project A Study in Explanatory Power at the University of Duisburg-Essen as well as by a fellowship (Stipendium nach dem Landesgraduiertenförderungsgesetz) sponsored by the State of Baden-Württemberg (Germany).

References

  1. BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Brössel, P., Eder, A.-M. A., & Huber, F. (2013). Evidential support and instrumental rationality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87, 279–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Eder, A.-M. A. (2015). A study on the foundations of theories of epistemically rational belief and some applications. (Unpublished Manuscript).Google Scholar
  4. Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 15–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Field, H. (2009). What is the normative role of logic. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 83, 251–268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Foley, R. (1992). The epistemology of belief and the epistemology of degrees of belief. American Philosophical Quarterly, 29, 111–124.Google Scholar
  7. Goldman, A. (1980). The internalist conception of justification. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 27–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Harman, G. (2002). Internal critique: A logic is not a theory of reasoning and a theory of reasoning is not a logic. In D. M. Gabbay, et al. (Eds.), Handbook of the logic of argument and inference: The turn towards the practical (Vol. 1, pp. 171–186). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  9. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: A critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 612–640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kelly, T. (2007). Evidence and normativity: Reply to Leite. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75, 465–474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kelly, T. (2014). Evidence can be permissive. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 298–312). Hoboken: Wiley.Google Scholar
  13. Kroedel, T. (2012). The lottery paradox, epistemic justification and permissibility. Analysis, 72, 57–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Kroedel, T. (2013a). The permissibility solution of the lottery paradox—Reply to Littlejohn. Logos and Episteme, 4, 103–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Kroedel, T. (2013b). Why epistemic permissions don’t agglomerate—Another reply to Littlejohn. Logos and Episteme, 4, 451–455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kyburg, H. E. (1961). Probability and the logic of rational belief. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Leitgeb, H. (2014). The review paradox: On the diachronic costs of not closing rational belief under conjunction. Noûs, 48, 781–793.Google Scholar
  18. Levi, I. (1967). Gambling with the Truth: An essay on induction and the aims of science. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Littlejohn, C. (2012). Lotteries, probabilities, and permissions. Logos and Episteme, 3, 509–514.Google Scholar
  20. Littlejohn, C. (2013). Don’t know, don’t believe: Reply to Kroedel. Logos and Episteme, 4, 231–238.Google Scholar
  21. Makinson, D. C. (1965). Paradox of the preface. Analysis, 25, 205–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Moretti, L. (2014). The dogmatist, Moore’s proof and transmission failure. Analysis, 74, 382–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Nelson, M. (2010). We have no positive epistemic duties. Mind, 119, 83–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Pollock, J. (1987). Epistemic norms. Synthese, 71, 61–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Poston, T. (2008). Internalism and externalism in epistemology. In J. Fieser & B. Dowden (Eds.), Internet encylopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/int-ext/
  26. Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief: Ranking theory and its philosophical applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Steup, M. (2000). Doxastic voluntarism and epistemic deontology. Acta Analytica, 15, 25–56.Google Scholar
  28. Steup, M. (2012). Epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/epistemology/
  29. van Fraassen, B. (1985). Empiricism in the philosophy of science. In P. M. Churchland & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism, with a Reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (pp. 245–308). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  30. van Fraassen, B. (2000). The false hopes of traditional epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60, 253–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. White, R. (2005). Epistemic permissiveness. Philosophical Perspective, 19, 445–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. White, R. (2014). Evidence cannot be permissive. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 312–323). Hoboken: Wiley.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentUniversity Duisburg-EssenEssenGermany

Personalised recommendations