Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 79, Supplement 6, pp 1151–1168 | Cite as

The Problem of Rational Knowledge

  • Mark JagoEmail author
Original Article

Abstract

Real-world agents do not know all consequences of what they know. But we are reluctant to say that a rational agent can fail to know some trivial consequence of what she knows. Since every consequence of what she knows can be reached via chains of trivial cot be dismissed easily, as some have attempted to do. Rather, a solution must give adequate weight to the normative requirements on rational agents’ epistemic states, without treating those agents as mathematically ideal reasoners. I’ll argue that agents can fail to know trivial consequences of what they know, but never determinately. Such cases are epistemic oversights on behalf of the agent in question, and the facts about epistemic oversights are always indeterminate facts. As a result, we are never in a position to assert that such-and-such constitutes an epistemic oversight for agent i (for we may rationally assert only determinate truths). I then develop formal epistemic models according to which epistemic accessibility relations are vague. Given these models, we can show that epistemic oversights always concern indeterminate cases of knowledge.

Keywords

Belief State Modus Ponens Trivial Consequence Paraconsistent Logic Epistemic Possibility 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Belnap, N. (1977). A useful four-valued logic. In J. Dunn & G. Epstein (Eds.), Modern use of multiple-valued logic. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  2. Bjerring, J. (2011). Impossible worlds and logical omniscience: an impossibility result. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-011-0038-y.
  3. Chalmers, D. (2010). The nature of epistemic space. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Fagin, R., & Halpern, J. (1988). Belief, awareness and limited reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 34, 39–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Fagin, R., Halpern, J., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. (1995). Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
  6. Fagin, R., Halpern, J., & Vardi, M. (1990). A nonstandard approach to the logical omniscience problem. In R. Parikh (Ed.), Proceedings of the 3rd conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge (pp. 41–55). Burlington: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  7. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Hintikka, J. (1975). Impossible possible worlds vindicated. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 475–484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Jago, M. (2009). Logical information and epistemic space. Synthese, 167(2), 327–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Jago, M. (2012). Constructing worlds. Synthese, 189(1), 59–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Jago, M. (2013). The content of deduction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(2), 317–334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kleene, S.C. (2002). Mathematical logic. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  13. Lakemeyer, G. (1986). Steps towards a first-order logic of explicit and implicit belief. In J. Y. Halpern (Ed.), Proceedings of the first conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge (pp. 325–340) San Francisco, California: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  14. Lakemeyer G. (1987). Tractable metareasoning in propositional logic of belief. In Proceedings of the 10th international joint conference on artificial intelligence, pp. 401–408.Google Scholar
  15. Levesque, H. J. (1984). A logic of implicit and explicit belief. In Proceedings of the 4th national conference on artificial intelligence, pp. 198–202.Google Scholar
  16. Lewis, D. (1982). Logic for equivocators. Noûs, 16(3), 431–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Lewis, D. (2004). Letters to priest and beall. In B. Armo-Garb, J. Beall & G. Priest & (Eds.), The law of non-contradiction—New philosophical essays (pp. 176–177). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Rantala, V. (1975). Urn models. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 455–474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Rantala, V. (1982). Impossible worlds semantics and logical omniscience. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 35, 18–24.Google Scholar
  21. Restall, G. (2005). Multiple conclusions. In Proceedings of the 12th international congress of logic, methodology and philosophy of science, pp. 189–205.Google Scholar
  22. Restall, G. (2008a). Assertion and denial, commitment and entitlement, and incompatibility (and some consequence). Studies in Logic, 1, 26–36.Google Scholar
  23. Restall, G. (2008b). Assertion, denial and non-classical theories. Proceedings of the 4th world congress of paraconsistency, Melbourne.Google Scholar
  24. Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Williamson, T. (1992). Inexact knowledge. Mind, 101(402), 217–242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of NottinghamNottinghamUK

Personalised recommendations